v Pa ee ee ou oF * * * dedi ee ee i Ae es Sone) . OV G0) Pres » ie Le oe vw ee . . i ’ pet ' ee ’ he, Pe A ae oe es ei Prue vere BO oO ne . ’ *? - . a TOP ones st ei ey + ete ree? v Syn phen 8 7 ¥ + ev Orne e Avrs DAP ae caw eewes ‘ 99 08-8 ‘eee BF omer re 0's 8 PEP Se re ee y *UPOR ire Sah a er “a dd ah hE oa oy hate ames AT RLY v oo rey ‘? a ; eb oy . res ey ; eee ae =. PEOS 6 ees - Av. Pee 7 es vee . sa A woe el y , . ae ee eee i ’ “Seve ; ‘ . ee eee ee "9 ’ ; ’ ‘ . 7 ’ ad ; he? ’ « ev ‘ ’ vs ‘ ’ ee +? eer we we ’ . rie ov x Wt O98 > Be "eG if : ; . ° ; ‘ e-¥ aren “es ’ c " & ‘ ee oi ver “ » . a . a ree wy ’ ’ ‘ ; o:¢ <> ‘ > ; SuLL : . ee ee » a - * eyeore ’ “a ey 7 . - . GTO , didiad is y ' ve - «ee y : ‘ om ee » 4 © ; + ° . ~ ‘ oF ‘ ’ ww ISON OD ? / ya ee . ? , : - . eS a3 ‘ oa ” > a ‘ ‘ - : . J ver a eBe - 62 fee Set ) ‘ 45% . ; ; ~ > Pe 4 ee ; . ; 4 F 4 a ee Y - whe i , ve : ” 4 J > o-+ bey ; ¥ +08 ee oo < ' ; re f " - 3 sites . , ; , ’ Pere ee t « + = » ‘ . se 3 ‘ o ay _ . ; r-9 Oog . oe 2. P andy - : P ' ‘ v4 : " “s 4 SY ’ ’ a OOF OU OG ’ * . : : P Por? w Ps ‘ f : : ‘ee 2 s , . ‘% ‘ee ’ ree sad . ‘ ‘ ) 2 ; Ag 9 eg y . “* ‘* ‘ ’ " ‘ 2 0:9 " : ee y ~ ; . + erp ewe L 3g C COCLIELO IOLA es | Sara Rn Cee aay jy tr a as oe P x : ' : : Pe ye pot rey ers : : ’ ¥; , > . ’ g ’ “ - ’ ‘ gop Tt oe ’ 4 , , , . : re . ‘ ” : : . " . 4 . 4 ‘ . . ‘ : ri ‘ee ‘ ; ’ ’ “? : ‘ i tees O1LNOHOL 4O ALISH3AINN . ‘ , ie > ‘ ‘ ; ‘ - ; , “ > os & ne a ee ee 7 to ene an | A ‘penae. bay eee a ee “ae abe PEE EM Bie Yllg Mr! eM yr eee ale Hr Gagne gs cage ene Pieter. . Poe epee tn ne ee ce Minas ae Re A, reer 2AM aha oh ane ale ra “s : cae > ¢ F 4 3 EA Zo 4 we & rt *) a? S re 6 a8 ji 3 ~ i soe . FRANCIS BACON : OF VERULAM., , ey « I28 | eTRISF las . Eo 3 FRANCES BACON OF VERULAM. REALISTIC PHILOSOPHY AND ITS AGE. BY KUNO FISCHER. TRANSLATED FROM THE GERMAN BY JOHN OXENFORD. ** Veritas Temporis filia.’’ Nov, Ora. I. 84. LONDON: LONGMAN, BROWN, GREEN, LONGMANS, & ROBERTS. 1857. TRANSLATOR’S PREFACE, My chief object in translating Dr. Fischer’s excellent work on Bacon and the realistic phi- losophy, was to lay before English readers a brief but complete digest of two books, which, all- | important as they are in the history of science, are most assuredly commended much oftener than they are read. Whatever veneration may be paid in England to the treatise “De Augmentis Sci- entiarum” and to the ‘“ Novum Organum,” few indeed are the students who would elaborate for themselves so perfect a summary of the doctrines contained in those celebrated productions as is presented by Dr. Fischer within the space of a few brief chapters. Whether his estimate of the English philosopher merits approval or not, the value of the descriptive part of his book A3 vl TRANSLATOR’S PREFACE. remains indubitable. To heighten this value, and to bring Bacon more immediately before the reader than he is in the original German, I have given extracts in the margin, where Dr. Fischer has only given references; and wherever it has been possible, I have introduced the Baconian words into the text. In performing the work of translation, I have endeavoured, as much as possible, to make my version readable. Dr. Fischer does not, it is true, indulge in those technicalities which have been introduced into the German language by the suc- cessors of Kant; indeed, with the exception of a few Kantisms, generally explained by the context, his book is free from technicalities altogether. Nevertheless, the German language, indepen- dently of the influence of philosophical schools, contains expressions which cannot be verbally rendered without producing a result totally unin- telligible to any one but a German scholar. I have, therefore, endeavoured to render sentence for sentence rather than word for word, certain that I should thus render a greater service to the TRANSLATOR’S PREFACE. Vil generality of readers than by encumbering the text with a number of strange compounds, utterly at variance with the genius of the English language. Some readers, perhaps, will think I might have gone farther in this respect, and adopted more familiar expressions than (for instance) “ realistic” and “naturalistic.” To these I reply, that the abolition of all apparently pedantic expressions would produce ambiguity. To ordinary ears, “real philosophy ”’ would sound as the antithesis to sham philosophy, rather than to any form of idealism. Where Dr. Fischer’s marginal references have obviously been made for a German public only, I have taken the liberty to omit them, and in some cases, where I thought further elucidation neces- sary, I have added a note, signed with my own initials. "With the same view, I have inserted two appendices, J. O. London: September, 1857. A4 “ i panels: REE bss 2a AUTHOR’S PREFACE. Tue theatre of modern philosophy is a field of battle, wherein two opposite and hostile ten- dencies— Realism and Idealism—contend with each other in asserting claims to truth. These tendencies are not merely systems, but hinds of philosophy that in no age but a modern one could become so conscious of their mutual differ- ence, or so definitely and clearly express it. If we were to compare scientific with dramatic op- position, the realists and idealists would be the two adverse choruses in the drama of modern philosophy. The opposite parties will not be silent until their union is effected, until the modes of thought, now strained against each other, be- come so interpenetrated, that both are saturated alike. For each lives only in the weaknesses and defects of its adversary. The boundaries between them will be passed when they are clearly under- stood; that is to say, when each party recognises the strength of its adversary, and appropriates it to x AUTHOR'S PREFACE. itself. Many attempts to produce this result have been made during the first period of our philo- sophy. If we accurately consider the matter, we shall find that realism and idealism, from the time of their modern origin, have described not parallel but convergent paths, which, at the same time, have met at one common point. This point at which the idealistic and realistic ten- dencies crossed, as at a common vertex, was the Kantian philosophy, which has taken account of them both and united them in their elements. In this, as indeed in every respect, it has set up a standard, which must serve as a polar star to all subsequent philosophy. If, at the present day, we are asked, how we shall follow the right track in philosophy, we must answer, by a most ac- curate study of Kant. Since his time there has not been a philosopher of importance, who has not desired to be at once a realist and an idealist. If the name had been sufficient, the gre.‘ and all-pervading problem that occupies the mind of modern philosophy would have already been solved more than once. All these self- called ideal-reai. -ic, or real-idealistic, attempts do not, indeed, prove that they have solved the problem, but they prove that it is recognised and admitted. It is sufficient for us to establish the fact that the problem exists, and, without opposi- tion worthy of note, is everywhere regarded as all- AUTHOR'S PREFACE. xi important.* Nevertheless the contest continues, and the idealistic systems of the Germans, however realistic they would appear, have always found realism arrayed against them. The two tenden- cies are again divergent, and the divergency is not to be got rid of by any new name or formula. German idealism would have been much bene- fited if it had made itself thoroughly acquainted with its adversary, and learned to appropriate the strength of that adversary to itself, in order to shun the more securely the accompanying defects. Our German idealists have no right to treat the English empirical philosophers with so much su- perciliousness ; and with a few words to consign them to the contempt of their disciples, as mere “unspeculative ” intellects, more especially as Leibnitz by no means thought it beneath him to honour Locke with a close examination, but by his “Nouveaux Essais sur ’Entendement Humain,” did greater service to German philosophy than alt the philosophical writings that appeared amos us prior to Kant’s “Critique of Pure Reason.” His example has not been followed. If German philosophy is looked upon in Engiand and France as German dreaming, we oug't not to repay one wrong with another, but are bound to deprive the » * “ Giiltig,” literally “valid ;” but the word would hardly be forcible enough in this place. —J. O. xil AUTHOR’S PREFACE. reproach of its force, by showing that, without dreaming and without prejudice, we recognise foreign philosophers, and appreciate them to the extent of their deserts, especially as in matters of science every act of injustice betokens ignorance. Francis Bacon is still regarded by his country- men as the greatest philosopher of England; and in this opinion they are perfectly right. He is the founder of that philosophy which is called the — realistic, which exercised so powerful an influence _ upon even Leibnitz and Kant, to which Kant especially was indebted for the last impulses to his epoch-making works, and to which France paid homage in the eighteenth century. Now this very philosopher, of the first rank among the realists, is not only still without that acknow- ledgment in Germany, which is his due, but he has never even been treated of by any German in a thorough and satisfactory manner. In our histories and compendia of modern philosophy, Bacon plays either no part at all, or at best but a very insignificant and subordinate part, as one among others who made his appearance during the strange transition from medieval to modern philosophy. Some rank him with the natural philosophers of Italy, with whom Bacon, if we regard the principal point, has scarcely more in common than the expression “natural philoso- 3) pher;” and from whom he is distinguished not AUTHOR’S PREFACE. xii only by his mode of thought, which is entirely different, but also by his relation to antiquity, which in this case offers a fitting standard. Others express his relation to modern philosophy by placing him by the side of the German mystic, Jacob Béhme, with whom he has nothing in common but the first letter of his name. Ina word, most of the opinions respecting Bacon, which are uttered among the Germans, especially those most prominent, are as superficial as they are unsatisfactory and incorrect. If this had not been the case I should have had some reasons the less for writing this book, in which I endeavour to do justice to the importance of Bacon. It may be objected that the points of contact between the German and English philosophy— between Idealism and Realism—are less to be found in Bacon himself, than in some of his suc- cessors ; that it was not Bacon, but Hume, who influenced Kant, not Bacon, but Locke, who in- fluenced Leibnitz; that Spinoza, if he was affected by the English at all, was influenced not by Bacon but by Hobbes; and (as is well known) invariably spoke of Bacon in terms of contempt. To this I shall answer that it was Bacon who was opposed by Descartes, the acknowledged founder of dogmatical idealism. As for those realists, who have come into contact with the op- posite philosophy, as represented by Spinoza, +) XIV AUTHOR’S PREFACE, Leibnitz, and Kant, this work is intended to prove that the Hobbes, Lockes and Humes, are all descendants from Bacon ; that in him they all took root, and that without him they cannot be truly explained and accounted for, but merely be un- derstood in a fragmentary and cursory manner. _ Bacon con is the < creator of the realistic philosophy, the period of which is throughout a . development of Baconian genius, so that every one of its forma- tions is a metamorphosis of the Baconian philo- sophy. To this day yealism has had on its side who | en ae the true realistic ey ex- ulting in all its fulness of life, so broadly and at the same time so characteristically ; so circum- spectly, and at the same time under such an ideal aspect, and so high in its aspirations; no one in whom the lhmits of this mind are so definitely and naturally exhibited. Bacon’s phi- losophy is the liveliest est_ expression of realism, and After the systems of a ‘Spincaa and a Lailnita had long influenced me, filled my thoughts, and, as it were, absorbed me into themselves, the occupa- tion with the works of Bacon seemed to me like a new life, the fruits of which I collected in this volume. If I resign myself to the impression which is made by the Baconian philosophy as a whole, and which ever enlists the imagination on AUTHOR’S PREFACE. XV its side, I feel that there is something in it that in a most peculiar, and at the same time natural manner, distinguishes it from other works of European philosophy. In its orderly and vi- gorous fulness of life, that excludes all artificial regularity, this philosophy, like an English park, is totally free from all formal trimming ; or, to ex- press myself more cogently, it has, like the mighty island that gives it birth, nothing inland about it. I.can easily understand that Bacon is re- garded as the national English philosopher par excellence. Bacon stands in the same relation to Realism as that in which Descartes stands to dogmatic Idealism, Leibnitz to German “ enlightenment,” Kant to modern philosophy. He opens the path which others pursue, by following his traces. Hence I have treated him as much in detail, the others as concisely as possible, having adopted a similar plan in another work with respect to Leibnitz and the German philosophers of the eighteenth century. The scientific importance which I attach to Bacon, and the limits set by the plan of my work, may justify this mode of treatment. My purpose was to exhibit the Baconian philosophy, : and from this basis to deduce the theories of the philosophers who suc- ceeded him. If the English philosophy is depen- dent on B: Bacon, and the French philosophy of the eighteenth century dependent upon that, I could ~-s Pet XVi AUTHORS PREFACE. do no more with respect to the latter, than desig- nate the philosophical position which it occupies, especially as it is my design in another mono- graphy to review more closely the group of these French philosophers. While this book constitutes an independent work in itself, distinct from my general work on the history of modern philosophy, I will own that it is so far related to it that the subject treated there is not treated here. This is in accordance with the object of the book; for Bacon and his successors, although they form a necessary supple- ment to modern philosophy, and are not without influence on the idealistic branch of it, neverthe- less, have a separate and independent direction of their own, which does not decline towards the op- posite side. For the fact that both tendencies meet in Kant, is a result of the power of attraction that was exercised upon Kant by realism. : The relation of Bacon to antiquity, and that of his philosophy to Kant, were the first points of my subject to which I directed my glance, and which I made clear to myself. In the explana- tion of these points consisted my first attempts at the present work. This proved of practical im- portance to myself, as it was in a public lecture on the relation of Bacon to the ancients, that for the first time, after a lapse of seven years, I once AUTHOR’S PREFACE, . XvVil more discoursed from an academical chair. The philosophical faculty of Berlin, to whom I am in- debted for that memorable honour, will allow me, in remembrance of it, to dedicate to them this book with silent gratitude. Kuno FIiscuer. Heidelberg : 27th January, 1856. + &» CONTENTS. CHAPTER I. Bacon of Verulam as a Moral and Scientific Character CHAP. II. Invention as the Problem of the Baconian Philosophy x I. The Baconian Point of View.— Discovery and Invention : . ; II. The Dominion of Man pens Hominis) III. The Interpretation of Nature (Interpretatio Na- ture) . , ° , . . CHAP. III. Experience as the Means of Invention 7> I. The Idols * II. The Baconian euctichenn. ei ere and Deseletes a III, The Experimentalising Perception _1, Conviction opposed to Authority "2. Real opposed to Verbal Knowledge “3 Natural Analogy opposed to Human Analogy 4. Experiment opposed to the Delusion of the Senses. —Sense and Instrument . - 5. Efficient opposed to Final Causes . PAGE XxX CONTENTS. CHAP. IV. ~ True Induction as the Method of Experience I, The Comparison of several Instances Il. The Import of Negative Instances. — Experience Critical Il. Induction and imedaction in ye Bacohien Prerogative Instances as Aids to Induction. — Natural Science CHAP. ‘VY. Analogies as Prerogative Instances L The Defects of the Baconian Method II. The Prerogative Instances . Til. Natural Analogies CHAP. VI. The Philosophy of Bacon in its Relation to the Philosophy preceding it : I. The Practical ene Beenie and secpiciant II. The Physical Foundation : III. The Antiformal Tendency . : > 1. Bacon’s Antagonism to Aristotle . \ Syllogism ‘ Experience Syllogism and eperionee 2, Bacon’s Opposition and Affinity to Plato.— His Opinion of Plato and Aristotle The Platonic Idealism . The Platonic Method . 3. The Affinity of Bacon to Democritus aa the Atomists PAGE 96 97 101 112 116 119 121 125 140 143 146 156 152 154 157 161 163 166 169 172 CONTENTS. \ CHAP. VIL The Baconian Philosophy in its Relation to Poetry : I. The Baconian Poetics . ° II. The Baconian Interpretation of the ‘Kelas Myths.—The Fable of Eros . III. Greek and Roman EL Hadon and Shakspeare . ° é . CHAP. VIII. “ The Baconian Philosophy as the “ Instauratio Magna” of Science. — Organon and Encyclopedia . , ° CHAP. IX. The Baconian nee as an Encyclopedia of the Sciences . ° ° ‘ ‘ ° History ‘ : ° ° ‘ . Science ‘ ‘ I, Fundamental Philosophy. Bay eee i , Il. Natural Theology : ; é ; III. Natural Philosophy , : . 1, Theoretical Natural Philosophy ‘ . Physics . . , ‘ . Metaphysics . ‘ . 2. Practical Natural Philosophy : . 3. Mathematics ‘ é ° IV. Anthropology . : R ° : | 1. Physiology . : . ‘ 2. Psychology . , ‘ Vv 3. Logic ° é . , ‘ $4. Ethics J 5. Politics . . é ; ‘ PAGE 181 182 191 200 214 XxXil CONTENTS. CHAP. X. PAGE The Baconian Philosophy in its Relation to Religion . 290 I. The Separation between Reason and the Faith in Revelation. — Bacon and Tertullian eS) Il. Bacon’s Position with regard to Religion. — Contradiction and Solution . : . 298 1. The Theoretical View : : . 3802 2. The Practical View : : - O07 3. The Political View. ° é eg Bt 4. The Negative View ° : - 16 + 5. Bacon’s own Religious Sentiments . . 320 III. Diversity of Opinion respecting the Religious Views of Bacon. —Bacon and De Maistre . 324 CHAP. XI. The Baconian Principle of Faith in its Development . 84) J. Bacon and Bayle é : . 347 Il. The Anglo-Gallic “ Bnlightenmeut aes ae ay! Ill. The German “ Enlightenment ” : . 364 \ CHAP. XIL The Baconian Philosophy considered in its Relation to History and the Present Ps Ye I. Bacon’s Unhistorical Mode of Thought . . 374 II. Bacon and Macaulay. . ; oe CONTENTS. CHAP. XIIL*« The Progress of the Baconian Philosophy . - ‘ Empiria and Empirism : ; ° ‘ Empirism . ° , The Degrees of Development j in Empitien ‘ ° % I. The Atomism of Hobbes ‘ . 1. The State as an absolute Power 2. Morality and Religion as a Product of the State 3. The State as a Dene of wide II. The Sensualism of Locke : A 1. The Mind as a Tabula Rasa ; - 2. The Origin of Knowledge . : ° 8. Knowledge as a Product of Perception. — Sensation and Reflection . Iil. The French “Enlightenment” . IV. The so-called Idealism of Berkeley 1. Things as Perceptions 2. Perceptions as Things 3. The Deity is the Originator or our Pa ceptions . / ° ° V. The Scepticism of Wine. 1. The Objects of Knowledge . 2. Mathematics and Experience ° 8. Experience as a Product of Causality ; 4, Causality as a Product of Experience.— Custom and Faith ; 5. Custom as a Political Point of View VI. Hume’s Contradiction, and Kant’s Solution ° VIL. Bacon and Kant . A Pn ‘ . .. APPENDICES. Appendix A. (Referred to at p. 87) ‘ x ° Appendix B. (Referred to at p. 125) . “ ‘ XxX1l1 PAGE 406 408 411 414 416 418 420 425 435 437 440 442 451 454 456 460 463 468 469 470 473 476 483 494 497 503 505 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. CHAPTER I. BACON OF VERULAM AS A MORAL AND SCIENTIFIC CHARACTER, THE great intellectual achievements of a man are never so utterly distinct and separable from his life that he can be one person in his worldly career, and entirely another in the emanations of his mind. There is always a certain corre- spondence between the moral and the scientific character, and a mistake has been made when the character of Bacon has been excepted from the law of such an analogy. On the other hand, this law would be very wrongly applied if we attributed certain moral blemishes and delin- quencies affecting the life of Bacon to his scientific B 2 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. tendency, or from this tendency explained his moral course. Such a relation would be more than analogy, it would be a relation of cause and effect. Of such an immediate influence of the scientific upon the moral character, we can only speak with great caution, inasmuch as the moral character precedes the scientific in order of time, and human characters generally do not form themselves before the mirror of science. Nevertheless, there is between the two modes of expressing the mental individuality a natural homogeneity, which does not consist in the one following the other, but proceeds from this: that the genius of the man directs both to the same ends; for the genius of a great individual remains the same in all its utterances. Leibnitz, with his per- sonal character, could never have become a phi- losopher like Spinoza, nor Bacon like Descartes. The scientific direction pursued by Bacon fully corresponded to the peculiarity of his nature, to his wants and inclinations; and this direction was ereatly favoured by his moral disposition. Indeed, without such a cooperation of the mental powers, no great intellectual achievement is possible. It is wrong to blame or pity Bacon because, being a scientific character of the first rank, he was at the same time too ambitious to prefer the repose of a scientific life to the charms of high SCIENTIFIC AMBITION. 3 and influential office. Bacon himself, in his old age, has lamented this as a misfortune, but not as a weakness. The misfortune was his destiny, and likewise the destiny of his science. Not only he, but his science also, was too ambitious, too practical*, too much open to the world, to bury itself in seclusion. To advance the power of man is, On one occasion, called by Bacon himself the highest degree of ambition.f And this ambition belonged to his science; this effort was its first and last thought ; on account of this very ambition Bacon became a scientific character. His science was of a kind that could not endure a life of quiet retirement; it would rather float along the stream of the world than remain in a state of tranquil and secluded contemplation. «A \ talent is cultivated in seclusion, —a character — in the stream of the world.”{ To adopt these - words of Géthe, the home of Baconian science was the school, not of talent, but of character, — that is to say, it was worldly life on a grand scale. To this his philosophy and all his efforts were inclined. He decided early in life that a * “ Thatenlustig,” literally “delighting in action.”—J. O. t Compare Nov. Org. i. 129.; also vide Chap. IIL. of this work, t “ Es bildet ein Talent sich in der Stille, Sich ein Character in dem Strom der Welt.” 4 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. science secluded from the world must be narrow and sterile, and that the wretched phght from | which he wished to rescue philosophy was partly to be explained by the life of retirement usually | adopted by learned men. He judged that the knowledge of these persons was as narrow as their cells, as the convents and cloisters in which they were secluded, mm ignorance of the world, nature, and their own times. So diametrically—both from inclination and on principle —was the scientific mind of Bacon opposed to the condition of learn- ing that had continued down to his own time, that he necessarily felt an impulse to alter even its outward form of existence, and to exchange the life of the cloister for the life of the world. The student of the cell was transformed into a man of the world, who, both in science and in practical life, aimed at the same lofty goal of influential power. Doubtless his practical career demanded a heavy expenditure of time and labour; and thus there was so much less to bestow on scientific labour. But are we, on that account, to wish that Bacon had devoted his whole life, or the greater portion of it, to secluded science? This would be neither more nor less than wishing that Bacon had been endowed with another sort of scientific mind; that he had been another philo- sopher than he actually was; —this would be over- APPARENT CONTRADICTIONS. 5 looking the peculiar character of Baconian science. If we take this peculiar character into consi- deration, we find there is no contradiction implied in the fact that Bacon at the same time directed his energies both to science and to the acquisition of office. Even in the name of his science he could require the scholar to learn practical life from his own experience,—not merely theo- retically, as by a bird’s-eye view, but by actual participation. This, indeed, was what Bacon desired. In a scientific spirit he reproached the learned for their ordinary deficiency in a virtue of the understanding that could only be acquired in practical life,— namely, a knowledge of business and political prudence.* However, the manner in which Bacon displayed himself as a political character,— his own especial acts in this capacity seem diametrically opposed to his scientific greatness. This opposition has often been pointed out and lamented. Bacon has even been set up as an example to show how widely distinct from each other are the scientific * De Dign. et Augm. Scientiarum, lib. viii. cap. 2, (near the beginning). —“ Doctrinam de Negotiis pro rei momento tractavit adhuec nemo, cum magna tam litterarum quam litteratorum ex- istimationis jactura. Ab hac enim radice pullulet illud malum, quod notam eruditis inussit; nimirum, eruditionem et pru- dentiam civilem rard admodum conjungi.” B 3 6 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. and moral tendencies of a man—to how high a degree of internal contradiction the variance between these two characters can be brought. Mr. Macaulay, especially, has of late pushed this contradiction to such an extreme point that it seems insoluble, and the character of Bacon appears inexplicable. Macaulay pleads against Montagu on the subject of Bacon’s moral worth ; and it is well so to compare the two biographers (of whom the second is the panegyrist), that one may serve as a corrective to the other. For our own part, we shall neither defend nor attack Bacon’s character, but simply explain it, and hence we look here for that intrinsic harmony which belongs to every important character. Taking everything into consideration, we must confess that the contradiction between Bacon the philosopher and Bacon the political character does not appear to us so violent as it is represented by Macaulay. Neither was the one (to use the expression of Macaulay, who infelicitously cites a Baconian figure of speech),— neither was the one a “soaring angel,” nor the other a “ creeping snake.” Neither on the one side is there pure light, nor on the other is there mere shade, but on both sides is a compound of both. Of all the images that could be selected, none could be more unhappy than one which suggests a com- THE **CREEPING SNAKE.” 7 parison between Bacon’s philosophy and a winged angel. On the contrary, it was Bacon’s express and repeatedly avowed intention to make philo- sophy leave off her habit of flying; to pluck off her wings, and to put leaden weights in their place ; to hold her firmly down upon the ground, among earthly things, where Bacon himself lived, with all his inclinations. Bacon wished to transform philosophy, from a roving spirit that looks down- wards from above, into a human being, that cautiously ascends by the toilsome road of expe- rience. When Bacon, as a political character, takes the same road, and stumbles so often on this steep, rugged, intricate path of life, he does not, therefore, become a creeping snake. If every- thing that crept was necessarily a snake, it would be bad indeed; and I verily believe that whoever, under similar circumstances, pursues the same course as Bacon, will often find himself in such a strait that he will be compelled to creep. I well know the objections that will be made here. The blemishes of Bacon’s life are not mere human errors and weaknesses, but debased sentiments and political crimes. This I do not pretend to deny ; much less would I defend delinquencies which are proved beyond the possibility of doubt. The un- worthy sentiments are open to view; the crimes are acknowledged by Bacon himself; they have B 4 8 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. sullied his public name, and if they are designated in the hardest terms, I offer no objection ; only to me these single traits are not all the indices of his character. As far as I see, the character would have been precisely the same if the unworthy sentiments had not been so obviously manifest; if the crimes had not been committed. I could well imagine that with greater prudence Bacon might have avoided either the crimes themselves, or the whole weight of responsibility attached to them; but in that case I should not think a whit the better of him, or a whit the worse. He would then have been a more cunning, but not a better man. Indeed, a thorough-paced scoundrel, an accomplished plotter, would never have fallen into such open guilt. A human character should indeed be judged by its actions; but then the whole of these should be taken into the account. We should consider not only how a man deports himself in isolated cases, under the combined influence of all sorts of circum- stances, but how his moral elements are blended with each other. That which, in the natural dis- position of a character, is a mere weakness, may easily, through the force of circumstances, give rise to a bad action, or even a crime. By this the mode of action is certainly not improved, but neither does the element of the character become worse. When bad actions are equally base in their POLITICAL AMBITION. 9 outward appearance, the psychological connoisseur of the human may still detect an important dif- ference in the fundamental character of the de- linquents. If we pay no regard to the mixture of moral elements, we form a one-sided, abstract, and therefore incorrect judgment on the subject of character. Let the experiment be made with Bacon. Had he not been entangled in the affairs of Essex and Buckingham, we should have known none of those traits, on the strength of which Macaulay opposes the baseness of his moral personality to his scientific greatness, and Macaulay would have passed a more favourable judgment. But he would not have been right in so doing; for Bacon’s moral nature would still have been the same. We do not say this to excuse or defend, but simply to explain his character, which remains inexplicable if the apparent con- tradiction be admitted. What attached Bacon to Essex and Buckingham ?—not friendship, not ‘sympathy, but motives of self-interest. They were men of the most powerful influence; the former was the favourite of Elizabeth, the latter of James I. To rise in the offices of the state, Bacon desired and sought court favour; and this could not be obtained and preserved without such mediators. If he would become a man of 10 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. consequence, and accelerate his career, the favour of others was unfortunately a. more effective expedient than his own intrinsic talent. Now, ought Bacon to have avoided a practical career altogether? He was forced to pursue it by his inclinations, by his temperament, by the force of circumstances. At first he had to contend with the greatest obstacles; even his nearest rela- tives, the powerful Burleighs, threw impedi- ments in his way, and long held him down in a dependent position. If Bacon would not give up his practical aims, and vanish into a life of seclusion, repugnant to his nature, he must seek for assistance,—totally distinct from his own talents,—in the influence, protection, and patronage of others, and these he could not secure without courtly pliability,—without becoming a serviceable tool in the hands of the powerful. Here Bacon entered upon that hazardous and slippery path, which, though it brought him to the highest posts of honour, led him also into a multitude of perplexities and embarrassments, and at last caused his precipitate fall from the summit of prosperity to the depth of destruction. It was a hard and steep road that Bacon had to travel, as he rose from the poor barrister to the Keeper of the Seals and Lord Chancellor of MORAL LAXITY,. Il England ; from the unwearied suppliant to Baron Verulam and Viscount St. Alban. Nor did he find any difficulty in accommodating himself to the windings of the path, and in sacrificing so much of his moral independence as circumstances required. Nature had not formed him of stub- born material. He was easy and pliant to the highest degree,—made on purpose to guide himself by the course of circumstances, of which he took a very clear view. The temporibus servire cor- responded to his natural temperament, and to the tone of his philosophy, of which the fun- damental principle was to follow the times by a mode of thought really conformable to the times. Altogether, Bacon did not regard life with the conviction that it was a problem of eternal import, to be solved according to a moral rule, but rather as a game that could only be won by quickly-devised and judicious tactics. There are characters who affect to be easy, pliable, and subservient to the will of others, that they have the greater chance of becoming the reverse of all this; who apparently allow themselves to be governed, that their own rule may be rendered the more secure, and like the cunning pope seek the keys of power with stoop- ing heads. Among these hypocritical and really arbitrary characters Bacon is not to be enume- 12 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. rated. His ambition was of a yielding kind, and his natural honesty came often into collision with his political shrewdness. To-day, in conformity with his own convictions, he delivered a patriotic speech in Parliament against the subsidies*, and having thus offended the queen he did all he could to appease her wrath. He repented that he had made the speech; and we may be fully convinced that he felt- unfeigned sorrow on account of an impolitic act that was so much in the way of his plans. On another occasion he toiled to save the man who had been his benefactor; but when he saw that the queen’s good graces were at stake, he allowed his friend to fall, having only sought his favour because he had been the favourite of the queen. He always stooped as soon as he saw that he might knock his head by keeping it upright. ‘This spectacle of so great a mind in such a wavering and undignified condition is far from edifying; but even here we may find a trait that accompanies Bacon’s character through all his wanderings, that belongs to his peculiarities, and has its foundation in his inmost nature ;—I mean an extraordinary facility in helping himself, under * The speech referred to was made by Bacon in 1593 (1592 ? J. O.), as representative of Middlesex.— Author's note. ELASTICITY OF CHARACTER. 13 any circumstances, in passing over the difficulties of a route, and hurrying on as if nothing of any moment had occurred, as if no mark of evil were left in his track. In him every unpleasant sensa- tion was easily smoothed down, every loss, even moral loss,—nay, even that last of losses, the loss of a good name, was easily compensated. His life and his writings make upon us the same impression, that this man could find nothing difficult either to endure or to execute. In such a mind, even this facility is a species of strength, a proof of indestructible energy and vital power; a natural elasticity, which indeed appears like a weakness, whenever it encounters opposition. David Hume was right when he missed in Bacon that firmness of character which we ‘call the moral power of resistance. We know of no philosopher more elastic than Bacon. He possessed to the highest degree the power and the impulse to expand himself beyond all bounds, but the power of resistance he lacked ; he yielded to a pressure, and allowed himself to be driven into a corner by the overwhelming force of circumstances. He could augment and diminish, with the same natural facility, without being affected, either in his higher or his lower posi- tion, by an excessive sensibility, which in the one case would have stimulated his pride, in the aS 14 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. other would have too painfully depressed him. Hence it was that the man, who excelled all . others in intellectual power, and imprinted a - new form of mind upon his age, at the same time presented a soft material capable of receiving the impression from any hand that happened to be powerful. This elastic power constitutes, as it were, the type of his individuality, in which all his politics, his virtues as well as his foibles, harmonise with each other. Here we can perceive that his character is consistent with itself. From this point we explain the peculiar turns of his life, his vicissitudes, even his extremest aberrations. It is perfectly evident to us that such an intellec- tual power, fitted as it was to strive towards a great end, and at the same time to penetrate into minutia, could not fail to produce extraordinary results in the region of science; that it was especially made to awaken a new life in this region, and that, above all, it corresponded to Bacon’s own scientific tendency, namely, the progression from parti- culars to general laws. If we imagine the same power placed in the midst of social intercourse, we find that this rich, versatile mind, affable to every person, accessible to every form of life, con- tains within itself all the talents that constitute the agreeable companion. Bacon possessed by nature INTRINSIC HARMONY. 15 all those qualities which have a right to shine in society; he united the weighty with the light, not by deliberate art, but by dint of natural grace. His command over words was perfect, both in public orations and in private converse. According to the testimony of Ben Jonson, Bacon was an orator whom one never grew weary of hearing. But this very power, which in science and in social life finds so brilliant and lofty an expression, acquires quite another aspect when its acts are of a moral kind; the moral element is for such a form of individuality the most uncon- genial and the most dangerous. There is zo elastic morality ; and Bacon’s moral nature was as elastic, as facile, as completely directed towards practical ends, and as compliant with circumstances, as his intellect. It quite accorded with the key-note of his individuality. Here is the perceptible har- mony of his character, which has often escaped notice, or (as in the case of Mr. Macaulay) has been missed altogether. We see in Bacon’s moral character, as compared with his intellect, not a distinct being, but only the shadow of his indi- viduality, which grew larger as its substance increased in power and importance. Elastic morality is lax. Moral virtue demands, above everything, a firm, tough, obstinate power of resistance, for it consists in a victorious struggle 16 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. with the allurements and temptations of life. If this power of resistance has its fulcrum in the natural disposition of the individual, it is a talent. Now this moral talent was wanting in Bacon’s nature; and the virtue that corresponds to it was therefore wanting in his life. All the moral blemishes that disfigure his life have their real foundation in this absence of virtue; in this natural want of resisting power; in that mental facility which gave such extraordinary animation to his scientific, and so grievously crippled his moral energies. Bacon’s life has always appeared to me the strongest proof of the correctness of Leibnitz’s definition, according to which evil is the absence of good, and vice therefore is a moral weakness. Bacon was not vicious by nature. His moral disposition was the reverse of diabolical. It was in the highest degree facile, and therefore frail; through all the windings of his life it became no worse than it was by nature ;—1it was easily corrupt- ible. Indeed, when we see the general cor- ruption by which such a character was surrounded, we can scarcely wonder that it fell into sad perplexities and aberrations. There was no melancholy element in his disposition to render him more sensitive to the pressure of life; he could bear his lot easily; and even from that terrible blow that gave a mortal wound COOLNESS OF TEMPERAMENT. 17 to his honour, he recovered with astounding rapidity, and thenceforward, in voluntary seclu- sion, devoted all his powers to science. His feelings corresponded to his temperament. He had none of those violent and deep emotions that excite the soul, and carry it forcibly along; never did love or hatred wholly overpower him; his love was a cool inclination, his hatred a cool dislike. No mark of friendship or devotion could move him to give his whole heart; and, on the other hand, he was just as little roused by enmity. It was easy for him to abandon and even to persecute a fallen friend, for the sake of gaining the royal favour, or to contract a marriage, which offered no charm but wealth. Violent passions were as alien from his heart as the fallacies, which he termed “ idols,” were alien from his intellect. His was not a cold, but a cool nature, whose likes and dislikes kept themselves within the limits of equanimity. Thus, without love or devotion, he could be benevolent, affable, and forgiving; and, without hatred or malice, he could act as an enemy. To do him justice, we must say, regarding him from both sides, that his friendship was indeed without fidelity, but that, on the other hand, his enmity was without bitterness; that he took up and wielded both with equal facility; and that Cc 18 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. the very characteristic of his mind which ap- peared like infidelity and ingratitude where a friend was concerned, looked like magnanimity and clemency where an enemy was the party in question. He could be ungrateful to his bene- factors, but he could not be vindictive to his foes. He had none of those passions that belong to the genus of love, but he was equally free from the opposite emotions of hatred. Instances might be cited where Bacon acted without feeling, but it cannot be proved that he was ever prompted by envy. He could as easily close his heart to the ingratitude, as he could open it to acknowledge the merit of others. So right was Spinoza, when he called envy the converse of sympathy. If there were a thermometer to measure the intrinsic force of human passions, we should find, in the case of Bacon, that the degree of warmth belonging to his heart stood very close to zero. His practical ends were to him of more value than the dictates of his own feelings. When both were in harmony, we might be certain to find in Bacon one of the most amiable of men; but the least collision would at once destroy the equilibrium of his natural benevolence. If he were compelled to make a choice between the practical objects of his life and the promptings of his heart,— between his interest and his friend, INFIDELITY TO ESSEX. 19 —we may be perfectly sure that Bacon would always have given the preference to the former. He attempted, indeed, to effect a reconciliation between them, and would have been much pleased if his experiment had succeeded; but as soon as it had failed, and Bacon saw the impossibility of success, he made up his mind to sacrifice his friend, and this sacrifice was made with small compunction. We thus have a thorough explanation of the saddest episode of Bacon’s life,—of the part which he played as counsel for the Crown against the Earl of Essex. Here was the hardest collision into which his interests could be brought. It was a collision not between duty and inclination, but between selfishness and friendship. Essex had loved him with passionate affection, and had loaded him with a multitude of favours, which he had repaid with as much devotion as was com- patible with his passionless temperament. What he loved in Essex was not so much the friend as the powerful favourite, who was of service to him. The favourite fell, and Bacon’s friendship was put to a test that it could not stand. It failed in a manner that unhappily was as much in accord- ance with Bacon’s character as it is repulsive to our feelings, notwithstanding its consistency with our explanation of his moral disposition. He c 2 20 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. really made every effort to save Essex without danger to himself. The attempt failed; the pas- sionate and unlawful acts which the reckless Essex allowed himself to commit made this abso- lutely impossible. Bacon was forced to make a choice between him and the queen. He made such a choice as was consonant to his nature. It was the queen’s will that he should himself support the prosecution and publicly defend the execution of Essex after it had taken place. He did support the prosecution, he did write the defence; in both cases plainly showing that he did not act in accordance with his feelings, but had still only one motive, that of pleasing the queen. When she desired him to defend, by a written statement, the execution that had taken place, Bacon expressed his gratification that Her Majesty had “ taken a liking of his pen.” When under the government of James I. the friends of Essex regained their influence, Bacon did every- thing to obliterate the memory of this proceeding. He heartily congratulated the Earl of South- ampton on his liberation from the confinement to which friendship for Essex and participation in his fortunes had brought him; and the written avowal of Bacon on this occasion was very cha- racteristic and very true. He assured the Earl that the change of the throne had wrought in SUBSERVIENCE TO BUCKINGHAM. 21 him no other change than this, “that he could be safely that to him now which he had ¢éruly been before.” In these few lines Bacon has de- | picted himself with the most naive candour. We see how much this moral character was subject to external influences, how fitted it was to conform itself to every change of circum- stance. This moral pliability is not far removed from venality, which, indeed, it becomes as soon as motives are derived not from the conscience, but from the force of external relations: Devoid of rigid conscientiousness, and also devoid of those strong passions which rule the mind after a fashion of their own, such characters constantly succumb to the corrupting influences from with- out. On these alone does it depend what form the venality will take, and to what a degree it will mount. And the circumstances amid which Bacon lived as a powerful and likewise complaisant tool caused his natural venality to take the grossest form of bribery, and to be heightened to actual crime. There was nothing in his moral disposition that he could oppose to such pernicious agencies. He subjected himself and his high position as Lord Keeper of the Great Seal of England to the power and in- fluence of a courtier. Because Buckingham exercised the strongest influence over the king, © 3 22 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. so was his influence irresistible to Bacon. It was impossible to renounce the support of the influential courtier, and as little could Bacon guide the inconsiderate man by his own superior views. He therefore yielded to him, and became an accomplice in the wrongful acts by which Buckingham enriched himself, allowing him to grant patents for hard cash and sell monopolies, which did manifest injury to the country. What was still worse, he tolerated the interference of the royal favourite in his own judicial acts, and the decisions which he subscribed often emanated from Buckingham. Bacon knew well enough that corruption of the legal tribunals is one of the worst evils that can befal a state; nevertheless he allowed the Crown and its officers to interfere in suits, and to secure the favour of the judges for itself or its clients; he actually did that which, with his own correct views, he never should have permitted ; he allowed himself to be bribed, and sold his decisions. By these illegal means he is said to have gained a rich booty; his enemies estimated his spoils at 100,000 pounds. This rapacity did not arise from grovelling avarice, but from a reckless love of magnificence. Bacon, as far as his own person was concerned, was moderate and abstemious;. but he liked to keep up a magnificent establishment and make a bril- TASTE FOR LUXURY. 23 liant figure in society. Luxury offered fas- cinations which he could not resist; his rash expenditure exceeded his means, and thus he loaded himself with a weight of debt which he could only lighten by means of unlawful and unjustifiable gains. Here Bacon and his fortunes appear in a truly pitiful light, namely, with the stamp of mere vulgar recklessness upon them. To a life in which luxury, debt, and dishonesty, always logically enough connected, appear in inti- mate union, we attach, according to the laws of analogy and experience, a character that has nothing in common with greatness and independ- ence of mind. Nor did the pecuniary difficulties of Bacon begin with the lustre of his official posi- tion. It appears that he always had a taste for immoderate luxury. At any rate, we know that before the episode with Essex, a goldsmith caused him to be arrested in the street for debt. The fate of Bacon came upon him as the Ne- mesis of some hero of antiquity. It allowed him to rise to the highest pinnacle of felicity, that it might thence strike him down with rapid and ter- rific blows. In a few moments the proud edifice of his fortune, the edifice which he had carefully constructed with the toil of years, lay before him a disgraceful ruin. Under James I. he had, by the favour of that c4 24 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. monarch, mounted the highest steps of the state ladder. Knighted on James’s accession to the throne, Bacon became, in 1604, King’s Counsel with a salary, in 1607 Solicitor-General, in 1613 Attorney-General, in 1616 (through the influence of Buckingham) Counsellor of State, in 1617 Lord Keeper of the Great Seal, and in 1618 Lord High Chancellor of England.* While in London he led a brilliant life at York House. His vaca- tions he devoted to a Tusculan leisure at Gor- hambury, where he occupied himself with literary Jabours and gardening. Here he kept up a scientific intercourse with several persons, in- cluding Thomas Hobbes, whose vocation it was further to carry out the Baconian philosophy, and whom Mr. Macaulay terms the most “ vigorous and acute of human intellects.” When on the summit of his political career he was further elevated, with great ceremony on the part of the Court, to the dignities of Baron of Verulam and Viscount St. Alban. He held the highest state office in England; and the publication of his chef-@auvre, the “ Novum Organum,” in 1620, stamped him as the first philosophical writer of Europe. This was the moment when Bacon * The above dates are from the note to Dr. Rawley’s life, in Mr. Spedding’s edition. Dr. Fischer’s dates are not quite the same. CHARGE OF CORRUPTION. 25 stood upon the culminating point of power and felicity, and was justly respected and admired by the whole world. Three days after his investment with the title of Viscount St. Alban had taken place with all solemnity, a new parliament assembled. The public grievances were discussed,— the selfish and mischievous grants of monopolies and patents, and above all the abuses in the law-courts. The House of Commons elected a Committee to investigate these abuses. On the 15th of March, 1621, the president of the Committee* reported that the person against whom the charges were brought was no less a person than the Lord Chancellor himself, “a man,” he added, “so endued with all parts of nature and art, as that I will say no more of him, being not able to say enough.” The prosecution was carried on; the cases of bribery became more and more numerous; the articles of the charge were twenty-three in number. A copy of them was sent to Bacon that he might defend himself; and at last, all evasion being impossible, he sent to the House of Lords a written answer, which opened thus :— ‘“ Upon advised consideration of the charge, descending into my own conscience, and calling my memory * Sir Robert Phillips. —J. O. 26 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. to account so far as I am able, I do plainly and ingenuously confess that I am guilty of cor- ruption, and do renounce all defence, and put myself upon the grace and mercy of your lord- ships.” Overwhelmed with shame, the unhappy man shut himself up in his room, and when a deputation of the lords waited upon him, he be- sought them “to be merciful to a broken reed.” His confession of guilt was dictated not so much by contrition as by policy, for the king, who could not save him, advised him to declare him- self guilty. He was sentenced to imprisonment during the king’s pleasure, to a fine of 40,0002, with the additional punishment that he was to ‘be for ever incapable of any office, place, or employment in the state or commonwealth ; and never sit in parliament, nor come within the verge of the court.”* The sentence was more severe than the judges, who felt both admiration and pity for-the offender, and indeed it was only carried into execution so far as form required. After an imprisonment of no more than two days he was liberated by the king, the other penalties were also remitted, and he might even have re- sumed his seat in the House of Lords in the next session of parliament. However, he did not again * In the original this addition is briefly expressed by the words: “ Biirgerlicher Tod.”— J. O. LIFE AND SCIENCE. 27 make his appearance in public life, but passed the remainder of his days in solitary devotion to science among the woods of Gorhambury. If we now compare Bacon’s moral disposition with his scientific character, we shall find between the two not a puzzling contradiction, but, on the contrary, a natural analogy; only the very pe- culiarities that were injurious and perilous with respect to his practical life were advantageous to his scientific pursuits. As the elements of science and life are distinct from each other, the expres- sions of the scientific and the moral character must be likewise different, even where they both agree in their common source. To certain tempta- tions the mind that seeks after truth is never ex- posed. Certain rewards are beyond the power of science to bestow, and for such rewards the scien- tific character cannot think of acting. It is easy to understand that an excessively practical intellect, a mind that thirsts after power and distinction, will become selfish in the affairs of worldly life, and that such a mind, if endowed largely with pliability, scantily with power of resistance, will not shun crooked paths in order to attain its end, and will at last purchase worldly gain at any amount of moral loss. But put such a mind, with the intellectual force belonging to it, on the path of science; here also it will exhibit the same 28 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. traits of character that generally determine the form of its individuality, but without the dross with which it becomes sullied in the impure ele- ment of worldly life. The element of science is in itself pure. In science there are no such vices as selfishness and venality. To transplant a cha- racter from the moral into the scientific element, we must leave out all that will not admit of this operation,— every merely moral phenomenon. Such a phenomenon, in the case of Bacon, is the selfish and feeble character of his will. How could this peculiarity find a scientific expression ? What aliment could it derive from science? Mr. Macaulay says correctly enough:—* In his library all his rare powers were under the guidance of an honest ambition, of an enlarged philanthropy, of a sincere love of truth. There no temptation drew him away from the right course. Thomas Aquinas could pay no fees; Duns Scotus could confer no peerages. The Master of the Sentences had no rich reversions in his gift.” If we set aside the difference of the elements in which Bacon’s sci- entific and moral character move, the conformity between them strikes us at once. Even science itself is embraced by Bacon in a sense that in- dubitably expresses his whole moral peculiarity. The harmony is obvious. ‘To prove the assertion of an original philosopher of our own country, PRACTICAL VIEW OF SCIENCE. 29 that it is the will that produces the understand- ing*, I would cite Bacon as an example. His science harmonises altogether with the key-note of his individuality and his will. He directs it, as he directs his life, to practical ends; would bring it into a new and fruitful combination with worldly life, from which it has hitherto been se- parated. All his philosophical plans are designed to enrich science; to render it mighty, respected, influential, generally useful. It is to be a power among men,—a beneficent power, and therefore universally reverenced. But science can only enrich itself with knowledge; can only become powerful when this knowledge is useful, prac- tical, efficacious. Let us, then, imagine the idea of Bacon’s life transplanted into the region of sci- ence: to what could it direct its efforts but to the acquisition of a vast store of useful and potent knowledge? How can this treasure be acquired but by a dexterous intellect, with an eye to real life, and an aptitude for worldly experience? In- stead of the riches which he seeks, Bacon finds in the science that exists its very opposite; the deep- est poverty, scanty knowledge, and that empty and unserviceable, while, to complete the gene- ral wretchedness, there is an infatuated belief * Arthur Schopenhauer must be the philosopher here in- / tended.— J. O. 30 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. that all this is marvellous wealth. If Bacon, therefore, is to carry out his own will in science, no other course is left, but to deprive the science that already exists of its idle conceit, and, since it cannot become richer than it is, to erect a new profitable science in its place. Thus arises in his mind the idea of a scientific Instauratio Magna. ‘To enrich science he must reform it, open new sources to it, thoroughly change the mode of thought to which it has hitherto been accustomed. The tree of knowledge, which Bacon found, had ceased to bear fruit; nothing but dry leaves could be shaken from its branches, and with this occupation, as Bacon saw, the learned by profession employed themselves to their own infinite satisfaction. Bacon had made himself acquainted with scholastic learning, and to the question, as to what he had found in the books of the schools, he replied with the answer of Hamlet to Polonius : —“ Words — words— words.” This dead, antiquated word- learning was, if he could carry out his intent, to be suc- ceeded by a new, fruitful science, springing up with youthful life. From the character of Bacon we may infer in 'what sense, and in what sense only, he could reform science. Open to the world, greedy for honour and distinction, full of interest for pub- & COOLNESS OF TEMPERAMENT. 31 lic life, as he himself was, he wished to make sci- | ence think practically, to direct her understanding | to realities alone, at the same time rendering this understanding so calm and subtle that it could contemplate things without prejudice, and investi- — gate them properly. For this purpose science — required a guiding method. Such a method Bacon laid down. It required a number of expedients to overcome the difficulties of the un- wonted route. Bacon discovered these expedients with his own peculiar adroitness; he gave his theory the movable, pliable form that could en- tirely accommodate itself to circumstances, al- ways discover the assailable side, find the proper handle for every case. This scientific tendency and the genius of Bacon were completely made for each other. I say again: the science, which Bacon proposed to himself, was highly favoured by his moral constitution. With respect to the pas- sions he was in a position of natural and therefore happy neutrality. His mind, never misled, never dazzled, never abandoned to the sway of ex- clusive affections, never chained to objects of the heart, could, with all the deeper interest and with all the greater clearness, direct itself to a com- prehensive whole. His cool heart supported his penetrating intellect. The science that Bacon contemplated required above everything a sober, 32 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. cold intellect, to which the coolness of his affec- ‘tions was highly favourable. In science he would only allow the anatomical analysis of things; the operation of the understanding, that armed with an instrument palpably enters into the interior of / asubject.* On this account he necessarily smo- | thered all feelings connected with the tastes or the affections. It may be remarked, by the way, that Bacon even desired vivisection for the in- terests of science. In a word, Bacon’s character was as practical, as cool, as supple as the science which he desired and E prescribed for his age. All those personal pecu- " liarities which cast so many shadows upon his life appear as so many bright places in his science, for which he was exactly fitted, not only by his head, but by his heart. A man’s merit must never be judged without his brains, nor the brains without the man. The lines which in Bacon mark the direction of his practical life and his science are not divergent, but parallel. The same man who, being at first a poor barrister, could make himself a powerful Lord Chancellor, also made * The German word is “ object,” but this is one of the cases in which that word is best rendered in English by “subject,” to which it generally stands in direct contradiction.—J. O. HOSTILITY TO SCHOLASTICISM. aa at first, a disciple of the Aristotelian philosophy as taught by the schoolmen. In the spheres both of politics and of science his aspiring genius was early manifested. When in 1577*, a boy of six- teen, he quitted the University of Cambridge, he already felt disgusted with the scholastic philo- sophy. We do not mean to maintain that he then saw his way plainly before him, and had clearly apprehended his plans of reform. A paper which might have furnished information on the subject is, unfortunately, lost. The later writings with which we are acquainted show that Bacon, at least to outward appearance, used great caution in abandoning the scholastic philosophy. In his “ Cogitata et Visat,” which was the first sketch of his “ Novum Organum,” Bacon ap- peared, for the first time, as the open and decided adversary of the scholastic philosophy, while the spirit that appears in the first sketch of his second great work, “De Dignitate et Augmentis Scientia- * According to Mr. Spedding, Bacon left Cambridge 1575,.— J. O. + Published in 1612. The work “ De Sapientia Veterum ” appeared in the same year. The chronology of Bacon’s works is sometimes uncertain, and is so in this case. We take Lord Campbell for our guide—Author’s note. [The “ Cogitata et Visa” was sent to Bodley in 1607, as can be proved by a letter of Bodley’s now extant —J. O.] D 34 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. rum,”* although foreign to the system of the schools, is not so unequivocally hostile. Even this trait is truly Baconian. He approached his goal step by step, looking far, and expressing himself cautiously. The part that Bacon in- tended to play in science, and the strong feeling he entertained of his own scientific power long before he boldly expressed his views, may be gathered from one of his letters to his uncle, Lord Burleigh, who probably, from selfish mo- tives, did not assist him in his political career. He writes in the year 1591: “I confess that I have as vast contemplative ends as I have moderate civil ends, for I have taken all knowledge to be my providence (province ?); and if I could purge it of two sorts of rovers, whereof the one with frivo- lous disputations, confutations, and verbosities ; the other, with blind experiments and auricular traditions and impostures, hath committed so many spoils; I hope I should bring in industrious ob- servations, grounded conclusions, and profitable inventions and discoveries, the best state of that * The first outline of this work bears the title, “ The Two Books of Francis Bacon of the Proficience and Advancement of Learning, Divine and Human,” and was published in 1605. The Latin translation, in which the work was considerably enlarged, appeared in nine books, under the title given in the text, in the year 1623.— Author’s note. PROGRESS IN LIFE AND SCIENCE. 35 providence (province ?).” What Bacon always desired in science is here expressed in a few words. His plans were as sober and practical as was possible in the region of science. But what thinker to this day can escape the imputation of being a dreamer? In such a light did Bacon, who wished to awaken science from her long dream, appear to the Burleighs; in such a light they represented him to Queen Elizabeth. Bacon’s political career exactly corresponded to his progress in science. His efforts in both were directed to great ends; in both he started with far-seeing projects, and achieved brilliant results. During a tour in France, whither, after leaving Cambridge, he accompanied the English ambassador*, he wrote, at the early age of nine- teen, a treatise on the state of Europe (“ De Statu Europe”). In 1580f the death of his father called him back; and soon afterwards he drew up his first philosophical sketch, which has not been preserved, and which bears the pompous title, “Temporis partum Maximum.” By his “ Essays,” published in 1597, he became one of the most widely read and popular authors in England. In the reign of James I. he rose in * Sir Amyas Paulet.—J. O. + According to Mr. Spedding, in February, 1578-9. D 2 36 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. philosophical importance as he rose in office. The sketch of his “ Novum Organum,” entitled ‘ Co- ’ appeared in the year when he gitata et Visa,’ was made Attorney-General, and the “ Novum Organum ” itself crowned his philosophical career at the very moment when his political career had ended with the dignity of Chancellor. If Bacon had a passion which sincerely and powerfully occupied his mind, it was the passion for science alone. Science was the only friend to whom he remained true; she accompanied him through his restless and busy life, and to her did the ever-active man return in the hours of his leisure. The thirst for science was his greatest ambition ; this alone he could never satisfy ; and its gratification constituted the real purpose and the purest felicity of his life. This passion con- soled and elevated the fallen man in his misfortunes after all his other ambitious efforts were hope- lessly thwarted, and it remained faithful to him till death. Science was Bacon’s last destiny, and even death bore witness to her fidelity. He died on the morning of Easter Sunday (April 9th) 1626, in consequence of a physical experiment * ; * Thinking that flesh might possibly be preserved as well in snow as in salt, he alighted from his coach at the bottom of Highgate Hill, while snow was lying on the ground, and buying SCIENCE HIS LAST DESTINY. 37 and one of the first sentences which, with his dying hand, he wrote to a friend, was this: “'The experiment succeeded excellently well.” a hen at the house of a poor woman, made the experiment on the spot. The snow chilled him, and not being able to return to Gray’s Inn, where he then resided, he was taken to the Earl of Arundel’s house, where he was put into a damp bed. The letter cited above was addressed to Lord Arundel, at whose house he died.—J. O, 38 CHAP. 3i, INVENTION AS THE PROBLEM OF THE BACONIAN PHILOSOPHY. We hasten to protest against an error respect- ing the Baconian philosophy that is widely diffused, and has taken deep root in Germany especially. The judgment formed of Bacon by the majority is to this effect, that he was a very fertile and suggestive, but by no means a consistent* thinker ; that the constitution of his philosophy is deficient in rigidly scientific connection and in logical se- quence of its different parts, and that, perhaps, this deficiency arises from internal causes. If by consistency they mean systematic form, they are quite right in denying it to the Baconian philosophy. There are philosophies that neither can nor are intended to be systems; and the Baconian is one of them. But system and econ- sistency are by no means identical. The syste- matic course of ideas is confined within narrow * “Kein consequenter Denker.” The word “consistent” is too strong to be an equivalent for “consequent,” but its exact force in this place will, I trust, be apparent from the context. —J. O. THE TWO MODES OF THOUGHT. 39 limits, and may be compared to a movement in a circular track; the (merely) consistent course, while it admits of logical deduction from its premises, can as well return upon itself, as admit of continuance in an infinite line. And this last is the course designedly taken by the Baconian philosophy ; it purposely avoids the systematic circle; but on the path it has chosen it pursues a logical and well-connected chain of thought. The very fact that this consistency in the Baconian philosophy has been so little under- stood and appreciated, renders it our especial duty to remove all doubts respecting its logical sound- ness. Two faults, that have been commonly committed in forming notions respecting Bacon, have led to the errors against which we are now contending. One fault consists in that hasty knowledge which ever dwells on the surface of the Baconian philosophy, and does not penetrate to its centre. This surface presents, indeed, a motley aspect. The second fault consists in beginning with a wrong point of view when following out Bacon’s course of ideas. Thus con- templated, the sequence certainly looks arbitrary enough. But of what sort is the contemplation ? Every rigid course of thought is determined by two points, that from which it proceeds, and that to which it tends; the former is the starting- D 4 40 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. point, the latter is the goal. The question is, which of these two points is first given, first apprehended in the mind; whether the thought first settles its starting-point, and then by a logical progress seeks its goal, or whether it first takes a clear view of its goal, and then con- siders which road it must pursue, and from what point it must set out? Logical thought is possible in both cases; but in the former case the mode of thought is different from that in the latter. There, my first thought is the premiss, and the further course of ideas consists solely of legiti- mate conclusions. Here, my first thought is the goal, and with respect to that my premiss 1s framed. Here I reason thus: this is my goal which stands as something necessary, and to be attained at all events; now such and such are the means which will bring me to that end, and these means themselves form a chain, the first link of which is my starting-point, and in this sense my premiss. Thus I reason from the goal to the starting-point. If my conclusions are rightly drawn, the course of my ideas is unquestionably logical (consequent), but its order and its direction are diametrically opposite to those of the other course of ideas, which from the given starting- point proceeds to the not-given goal. Both modes of thought are legitimate, but they differ ANALYTICAL MODE OF THOUGHT. 41 both in course and in tendency. Each has it: own point of view, and a method depending upon it. If the thought tends to a principle, its» guiding-point is an aziom*; if it tends to a goal that is to be attained, its guiding-point is a problem. Axioms suggest deductions; problems require solution. In the one case, I ask, what will follow from this principle? In the other, how shall I solve this problem? In both cases logical and methodical thought is required. The first method may be called that of deductions, the second that of solutions; the former is the synthetic, © = the latter the analytic method. For every de- duction is a synthesis, every solution is an analysis. | Now I maintain that a mind whose first thought is not a principle, but a problem to be solved, and which begins by proposing to itself a goal that is to be reached, —I maintain, I say, that its natural course of ideas must be followed and represented by us. First, it apprehends the pro- blem,—the goal that hovers before it in the dis- tance, —then the means of solution in a regular sequence down to the first link, which offers the scientific starting-point for the solution itself. Such a mind was the mind of Bacon. Nota * “ Grundsatz,.” Literally, “ fundamental proposition.” —J. O. 42 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. principle, but a problem constitutes the first thought and guiding-point of his whole philosophy. He first clearly apprehends his goal, then he reflects on the right means for infallibly attaining it. Through the whole course of his ideas he never turns his eyes from this goal, but always keeps it steadily in view. This setting up of goals belonged to the nature of his thought, which was therefore thoroughly analytical in its method. Bacon himself thought as he wished science in general to think; that is to say, he analysed things. His mind was made not to deduce from principles, but to solve problems ; and as Bacon thought, and indeed could alone think, in consequence of the peculiarity of his mind, so will he be regarded and represented by us,—as an analytical thinker. Every other mode of representing him is erroneous. His analytical reasoning is in the highest degree close and con- sistent. To discover in Bacon this character of a logical thinker, we must first suppose the problem with and in his mind, then seek the means of solution; first set up the goal, then discover and smooth the road to it. He is wrongly understood when, as is commonly the case, his thoughts are set forth synthetically, just as though the mode of his thinking resembled that of Descartes or Spinoza. We cannot give a synthe- SPIRIT OF BACON’S AGE. 43 tical representation of an analytical thinker without perverting his close and logical sequence of ideas into one that is arbitrary and unconnected, and thus greatly diminishing his philosophical worth ; for it is obvious that the analytical reasoning from such and such a proposed end to such and such means of attaining it is perfectly close and legitimate ; while, on the other hand, the synthetical reasoning from the means to the end will always appear loose and doubtful. The end despotically demands the appropriate means; on the other hand, the means can lead to many ends, and why should I infer one in particular? Such an inference would be arbitrary. If we assume that Bacon proposed to himself a problem that he could only solve by experience, and indeed only by one kind of experience, we must concede that he was per- fectly justified in elevating this to a principle. But if, on the other hand, Bacon had set out from experience as a first principle, innumerable roads might have led him from this point to innumerable ends. Why, then, did he choose this one parti- cular road, and this one particular end? Here what has just now appeared a necessary thought becomes a mere arbitrary caprice; and it is asa necessary sequence of thought that the Baconian philosophy is to be comprehended and exhibited. This is impossible, so long as it is synthetically 44 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. treated ; and that which to Bacon himself was an inference or an intermediate proposition is laid down as a fundamental principle. It is useless to repeat over and over again that Bacon set out from experience. We may just as well say that Columbus was a navigator, while the principal point is that he discovered America. Mere navigation was as little the leading thought of Columbus as mere experience was the leading thought of Bacon. l. I. Tue BaconrAn Point oF VIEW. DISCOVERY AND INVENTION. What is the point of view that commands the Baconian philosophy from the beginning to the end? Bacon found this point of view by com- prehending the problem of his age, and appro- priating it to himself. This age was shaken to its very vitals by those reformatory forces that, had been awakened in the preceding centuries. A revolution had made its appearance, which brought with it a change, both internal and external, in human affairs, and introduced a crisis in civilisation, through which tendencies and aims. were set before man totally different from those which he had previously followed. With his oy SPIRIT OF BACON’S AGR. 45 penetrating intellect, Bacon comprehended the altered physiognomy of his age; he sought for the ultimate causes of the change, and wished to make philosophy accord with it. For the new life and its impulses he wished to find a new cor- responding logic. Philosophy professes to be the love of truth. Bacon would suit this truth to the times. “It is the greatest weakness,” he says, **to attribute infinite credit to authors; but to refuse to Time, the author of all authors, and there- fore of all authority, its own prerogative. For -truth is rightly called the daughter of Time, not of authority.”* Again: “The opinion which men cherish of antiquity is altogether idle, and scarcely agrees with the term. For the old age and increasing years of the world should in truth be regarded as antiquity, and these are to be attri- buted to our times, not to that younger period of the world, such as it was in the days of the (so-called) ancients. For that period, with respect to ourselves, was ancient and older; with respect to the world itself, modern and younger.”+ * “Summz pusillanimitatis est authoribus infinita tribuere, authori autem authorum atque adeo omnis authoritatis, Tempori, jus suum denegare. Recte enim Veritas Temporis filia dicitur, non Authoritatis.”—Nov. Org. I. Aph. 84. Tt “De antiquitate autem, opinio quam homines de ipsa fovent negligens omnino est, et vix verbo ipsi congrua. Mundi enim senium et grandevitas pro antiquitate vere habenda sunt 3 que temporibus nostris tribui debent, non juniori xtati mundi, qualis — 46 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. The world in course of time has become older, richer, more comprehensive; science should be raised to suit this advanced state of the world. The limits of the material world are extended, and the intellectual world should not remain within its former boundaries. Thus the problem lproposed by Bacon is this:—So to extend the intellectual world (globus intellectualis) that it may be able to comprehend the material world, /such as the latter has become. “ It would be dis- ‘honourable to man if the regions of the material \ globe, viz. the lands, the seas, and the stars, should be so immensely revealed in our age, and yet the boundaries of the intellectual world should be confined to the discoveries and straits of the ancients.” * What now were the powers that set this new life | in motion, and put the middle ages “out of joint?” What were the mighty changes that stamped Bacon’s age as new, and fundamentally different from all that had preceded it? The political, sci- entific, and geographical conditions of the world apud antiquos fuit. Illa enim extas, respectu nostri antiqua et major, respectu mundi ipsius nova et minor fuit.”—Vov. Org. I. A ph. 84. * « Quin et turpe hominibus foret, si globi materialis tractus, terrarum videlicet, marium, astrorum, nostris temporibus im- mensum aperti et illustrati sint ; globi autem intellectualis fines | inter veterum inventa et angustias cohibeantur.”— Ibid. ii THE AGE OF REFORMS. 47 had one after another experienced a thorough reform. The material and intellectual position of mankind had become quite different since new expedients had removed the ancient limits of war, science, and navigation. The reform in the art of war was based upon the invention of gunpowder ; in science upon the invention of printing; in navigation upon the invention of the compass, without which the discovery of the new world, would have been impossible. Discovery, there-| fore, which was itself dependent upon invention, {,,(» constituted the civilising impulse of that new epoch, the spirit of which had penetrated Bacon. | Here Bacon discovers the secret of his time, its essential difference from antiquity and the middle ages — the goal to which science must henceforth be directed, and which philosophy should alone consider.* The inventive spirit of man had fashioned the new age. Hitherto this had been kept down, either because it was lightly esteemed, or because the means of liberating it had been wanting — because there was no intellect to comprehend and - regulate it. This, then, was the problem appre- hended by Bacon and proposed to his age: — The! subjection of science to the spirit of invention, and the liberation of this spirit from the chance * Compare “ De Augment. Scient.,” Lib, V., Cap. 2. PONE aban pn emtamiatii — 48 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. by which human inventions had previously been ' governed. He would establish a new logic, corre- sponding to the spirit of invention, by which man might deliberately and therefore more frequently achieve what he had previously achieved, as it were, by a mere chance, and therefore but seldom; that he might no longer find, but invent.* Exactly thus _ does Bacon formulise the problem_of his philo- sophy ; thus does he define it in his “ Cogitata. et Visa,” the concise programme to his “ Novum Organum.” Chance, which has hitherto been the cause_of inventions, is to be changed into design ; art (ars) is to take the place of luck (casus). “He thought that if many discoveries chance to men not seeking them, but otherwise employed, no one could doubt that if the same men were to seek discoveries, and that not by fits and starts, but by rule and order, many more things would neces- sarily be discovered. For though it may happen once or twice that some one by chance hits upon what has hitherto escaped him, while making every effort in the inquiry, yet without doubt the con- trary will happen in the long run. For chance works rarely, and tardily, and without order; but art constantly, rapidly, and in an orderly manner. * « Nicht finden, sondern erfinden.” There is an antithesis in the German words which cannot be reproduced in English. —J. O. BACON THE PHILOSOPHER OF INVENTION. 49 From those inventions also which have already been brought to light, he thought it might be . most truly conjectured respecting those that are yet hidden. But of these, that some were of such a kind that before they were discovered surmises concerning them would not readily occur to any one’s mind. For men commonly guess at new things by the example of the old, and the fancies they have derived from the latter; which mode of conjecture is most fallacious, since those things that are sought from the fountain-head do not necessarily flow through the accustomed channels. Thus, if some one before the invention of cannon had described it and its effects, and had said that a certain thing had been discovered by means of. which walls and the strongest fortifications might be shaken and battered down from a long dis- tance, men would certainly have formed many and various conjectures as to how the power of missive engines and machines might be multiplied _ by weights, wheels, and the like ; but the notion of a fiery wind would scarcely have occurred to any one, inasmuch as none of them could have seen an example of the sort, except perhaps in an earthquake or thunder-storm, which they would have rejected from consideration, as things not to be imitated. In the same manner, if before the invention of silken thread some one had talked in E 50 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. this fashion, affirming that there was a certain thread useful for dress and furniture, which far surpassed linen and woollen thread in fineness, and at the same time in strength, and also in gloss and softness, men would at once have begun to guess some sort of vegetable silk, or the more delicate hair of some animal, or the feathers and down of birds; whereas if any one had dropped a hint about a worm, he would certainly have been laughed to scorn for dreaming of some new webs of spiders. . . . . So awkward and ill-con- ditioned is the human mind in this case of in- vention, that in some things it is first diffident, and ever afterwards despises itself; so that first it seems incredible that such and such a thing could be invented, but after it has been invented it then seems incredible that it could have escaped the notice of man so long.”* Herein, then, consists Bacon’s principle, which is not defined with sufficient accuracy when, as is + commonly the case, he is called the “ Philosopher of Experience.” This expression is too vague and broad. Bacon is the philosopher of Invention; at least his only endeavour is philosophically to com- ‘ prehend and fortify the inventive spirit of man. From this point alone is his opposition to anti- * Cogitata et Visa, towards the end. THE THREE INVENTIONS. 51 quity and his new philosophy to be explained. This philosophy is as boundless as the region of invention. It is a movable instrument, not a fixed edifice of dogmas. It will not endure the confinement of system, the fetters of the school, the universality and completeness of theory. “Our determination is,” says Bacon, “ to try whether _ we can really lay firmer foundations and extend to a greater distance the limits of human power and dignity. And although, here and there, upon some special points we hold (as we think) more ~ true, more certain, and even more profitable tenets than those hitherto adopted, yet we offer no uni- versal or complete theory.” * Just as Plato detected, and, we may say, gave \| a logical expression to the spirit that dwelt in the poetry and art of the Greeks, so does Bacon direct his glance to the spirit of invention by which those discoveries were made that lie at the foun- dation of his age. The two philosophers bear the same relation to each other, and are as much dis- tinguished from each other as the ages in which * “Nobis constitutum est, experiri, an revera potentie et am- plitudinis humane firmiora fundamenta jacere ac fines in latius proferre possimus, Atque licet sparsim, et in aliquibus subjectis specialibus, longe veriora habeamus et certiora (ut arbi- tramur), atque etiam magis fructuosa, quam quibus homines adhue utuntur, tamen theoriam nullam universalem, aut inte. gram proponimus,”—Nov. Org. I. 116, E 2 52 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. they lived. Both direct their thoughts to human art. But the art to which the Greek philosopher | corresponds is the theoretic, self-sufficient art of & [rarer beauty in form; whereas that which finds its \representative in Bacon is the practical, inven- “tion-seeking art of human utility. Bacon himself declares, at the end of the first book of his « Novum Organum:” “ Let any one consider how . great is the difference between the life of man in the more polished countries of Europe, and that in some wild and barbarous region of the New Indies. He will deem the difference so great, that man may be rightly called a god unto man, not only on account of assistance and benefits, but also by a comparison of moral conditions. And this is the result not of the soil, not of the climate, not of any material body, but of the arts. It is profitable to note the force, effect, and con- sequences of things invented, which are nowhere more manifest than in these three, which were unknown to the ancients, and the beginnings of which, though recent, are obscure and without glory, viz., the art of printing, gunpowder, and the mariner’s compass. For these three have changed the aspect and condition of the whole earth; first, in literature; secondly, in warfare ; thirdly, in navigation. Whence innumerable changes have been derived, so that no empire, THE THREE INVENTIONS. 53 sect, or star seems to have exercised greater power or influence over human affairs than these mechanical inventions.” * We need only apprehend the idea of invention | Jf ; with analytical clearness to perceive the peculiar he Sa character of the Baconian philosophy, its object, ola a , its constitution, and its opposition to antiquity. Its sole object is to effect such a reform and extension of human science that this may turn to invention as its chief end, and to furnish science with an instrument which is as well fitted to make inventions, as a thermometer to measur heat. This instrument is the Logic of Inventio (ratio inveniendi), which makes the human under standing think in such a manner that it invent by necessity. Bacon explains inventive thought ; he seeks the method of invention. While he \ exhibits this, he formulises the spirit, and hits the central point of his age, more especially fortifying the peculiar talent and impulse of his own nation. The method of invention is the instrument with which Bacon would equip science, and render it capable of conquering the world. This in- strument is the “* Novum Organum,” which Bacon opposes to the “ Organon” of Aristotle. He bears the same relation to antiquity as his “ Organum” * “Rursus (si placet) reputet quispiam, quantum intersit,” &e.— Nov, Org. I. 129, E 3 wn if Pe a lad 54 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. to that of Aristotle. Bacon analyses invention as Aristotle analyses the form of propositions. Yl. Tue Dominion or Man. (REGNUM HOMINIS.) Invention is the aim of science; but what is the aim of invention? Usefulness to man, which consists in this, that the wants of his life are satisfied, his pleasures multiplied, and his power _gincreased. In one word, the dominion of man | over things is the highest and indeed the sole end of science; an end which can only be attained by means of inventions. Science should serve man,—should make him powerful. We cannot be made powerful otherwise than by science, for our power over things is solely based on our knowledge of their nature. Power consists in being able; but ability presupposes knowledge. Man can only act so far as he knows; his capa-. bility reaches only so far as his knowledge; or, as Bacon expresses himself at the commencement of the “ Novum Organum:” “ Human science and human power coincide.” * Science is, with Bacon, not the sole all-sufficient end in itself, but the means to a further end. This * “Scientia et potentia humana in idem coincidunt.”—Nov. Org. I. 3. THE DOMINION OF MAN. 55 re, Chine absolute end is the reign of man; the means to ios FB attain this end are given by invention; the means h ao vs of invention are furnished by science. Thus, in “| Bacon’s eyes, science is eminently practical ; its f Be measure is human life, its value consists in its © utility to man. The further the utility extends the greater is the invention, and the greater also are the value and power of the science that belongs to it. A science that is not practically useful is, in Bacon’s eyes, worth nothing. To his practical mind there is no self-sufficient theory estranged from life, and, on the other hand, there is nothing in human life that is to be deemed unworthy o investigation, or despised as an object for the understanding. Science no more distinguishes anything as low and vulgar, than the sun over our heads: ‘“ With regard to the meanness or even filthiness of those things, which, as Pliny says, are not to be mentioned without an apology, they must be admitted into Natural History, no less than those which are most magnificent and precious. Nor is Natural History polluted thereby; for the sun equally enters palaces and sewers, nor is he therefore polluted. We neither dedicate nor raise a capitol or pyramid to human pride, but we found a holy temple in the human mind, on the model of the universe. * This model, therefore, we follow. Whatever is worthy of E 4 56 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. being, is likewise worthy of knowledge, which is the image of being. Now the mean and splendid alike exist.” * Ill. Tue INTERPRETATION OF NATURE. (INTERPRETATIO NATURZ.) } { Karewlid’s é mvceet The reign of man is the aim of invention. But 4 g I . what are its means? What are the conditions ae “ander which alone invention is possible? We te ioe “cannot govern things without knowing them, and this knowledge, which at once renders objects transparent and subservient to us, can only be attained by long intercourse,—by intimate ac- quaintance. ‘To understand things we must asso- ciate with them, as with men,—live in the midst of them. “ We must,” says Bacon, “ bring men to particulars themselves, and their series and orders, and men must for awhile prevail upon themselves * “Quod vero ad rerum vilitatem attinet, vel etiam turpitudi- nem, quibus (ut ait Plinius) honos prefandus est ; ez res, non minus quam lautissimz et pretiosissime, in Historiam Natu- ralem recipiende sunt. Neque propterea polluitur Naturalis Historia ; sol enim szque palatia et cloacas ingreditur, neque tamen polluitur, Nos autem non Capitolium aliquod aut pyra- midem hominum superbiz dedicamus aut condimus, sed templum sanctum ad exemplar mundi in intellectu humano fundamus. Itaque exemplar sequimur. Nam quicquid essentia dignum est, id etiam scientia dignum, que est essentia imago. At vilia eque subsistunt atque lauta.”—Vov. Org. I. 120. THE INTERPRETATION OF NATURE. 57 to cast aside their (pre-conceived) notions, and to form an acquaintance with the things them- selves.”* This acquaintance or intercourse with things consists in experience. Just as a know- ledge of man is not to be obtained by construction from abstract notions ; so is it with the knowledge of things. Science should be the correct image of the world; this it can only become by an ex- perience of the world, that sojourns amid things and their movements and contemplates them all with a free, unprejudiced interest. In this sense/ Bacon makes experience the beginning of science. Science should invent, and the road to invention is shown by experience. In this sense is Bacon the philosopher of experience. Invention is the | end, and experience gives the means to that end. But mere experience is far from being invention in itself. Men have always had experiences, and have them every day. Why do they not invent in the same proportion? Simply because that is wanting which renders experience in- ventive? And by what means is experience rendered inventive? How must it be so ordered that invention is its involuntary and necessary * “Restat nobis modus tradendi unus et simplex, ut homines ad ipsa particularia et eorum series et ordines adducamus ; et ut illi rursus imperent sibi ad tempus abnegationem notionum, et cum rebus ipsis consuescere incipiant.”— Nov. Org. I. 36. 58 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. result? Under this definite formula does Bacon conceive his problem. ) Invention is an art which differs from esthetic art in this: that th Seems by means of the imagination uces something beautiful; the ; by means of the understanding, produces something useful. That which serves mankind, augments his power, subjects to him the power of things, is useful. The dangerous forces of nature are brought under our dominion, and rendered sub- servient to our uses, whether as rulers we employ them, or as victors ward them off. Lightning is a manifestation of natural force that threatens us; the lightning-conductor secures us against the threatened danger. Now to make an inven- tion of this kind,—in fact, to produce anything whatever by means of the understanding,—I must know all the requisite conditions. Every inven- tion is an application_of natural laws; and_to apply them it is necessary to know them. We must know what are the conditions of warmth to invent an instrument by which warmth may be produced. We must know the natural laws of lightning to present the conducting point to the destructive spark. And so in every case. Our. power over nature is based upon our knowledge of nature and her operative forces. If I am ignorant of the cause, how can I produce the KNOWLEDGE AND POWER. &9 effect? “ Knowledge and power,” says Bacon, ** coincide, since the ignorance of the cause frus- trates the effect. Nature can only be conquered by obedience ; and that which stands as the cause in contemplation becomes the rule in practice.” * Thus the right understanding of nature is the means by which experience leads to invention. If science is the foundation of all invention, so is the right understanding of nature, or natural scrence, the foundation of all knowledge. <« Al- though,” says Bacon, “in those very ages .in which the wit of men and literature flourished greatly or even moderately, the smallest part of human labour was bestowed upon Natural Philo- sophy, this very philosophy is nevertheless to be re- garded as the great mother of the sciences.”+ But natural science requires a correct explanation of nature,—a knowledge not only of her phenomena, * “Scientia et potentia humana in idem coincidunt, quia igno- ratio cause destituit effectum. Natura enim non nisi parendo vincitur ; et quod in contemplatione instar cause est, id in opera- tione instar regule est.”—Nov. Org. I. 3. t The above is rather a condensation than a translation of the passage (ov. Org. I. 79.) referred to, which is this : — “ At secundo loco se offert causa illa magni certe per omnia momenti: ea videlicet, quod per illas ipsas states, quibus hominum ingenia et liters maxime yel etiam mediocriter floru- erint, Naturalis Philosophia minimam partem humane opers sortita sit. Atque hee ipsa nihilominus pro magna scientiarum matre haberi debet.”—J. O, 60 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. but also of her laws; that is to say, a real inter- pretation. Here is the decisive point at which theory becomes practical, contemplative science becomes operative, knowledge becomes produc- tive, experience becomes inventive. And inven- tion itself forms the transition from the interpre- tation of nature to the dominion of man. Through science experience becomes invention, through invention science becomes human dominion. Our power rests upon our invention, and this upon our knowledge of things. In Bacon’s mind, power and knowledge, the dominion of man, and the scientific interpretation of nature, belong so essentially to each other, that he treats them as synonymous, and connects them with an “or” (sive). His “ Novum Organum” treats “ De Interpretatione Nature sive de Regno Hominis.” Our power consists in knowledge: in this truly philosophical proposition Bacon and Spinoza are agreed. According to Bacon, knowledge makes us inventive, and therefore powerful. According to Spinoza, knowledge makes us free by destroying the dominion of the passions, and the power of external things over ourselves. Here appears the difference of the directions taken by the two minds. With Spinoza, our power consists in free thought, which remains calmly contemplating the world, and is satisfied _ KNOWLEDGE AND POWER. 61 with that condition. With Bacon, our power consists in inventive thought, which exerts a practical influence over the state of the world, cul- tivating it and modifying it. The aim of Spinoza is attained when things cease to govern us; that of Bacon, when we govern the things. Bacon uses the power of knowledge practically, Spinoza theoretically ; both in the widest sense of the be wat term. Spinoza’s aim is contemplation ; culture A, i , is the aim of Bacon. as 62 CHAP. He EXPERIENCE AS THE MEANS OF INVENTION. Tue leading points in the Baconian philosophy stand thus:—Its ultimate purpose is the foun- dation and augmentation of human dominion ; the nearest means to that end are supplied by culture, which converts physical forces into in- struments fitted for man. Now there is no culture without invention, which produces the means of culture; no invention without science, which makes us acquainted with the laws of oe things; no science without natural philosophy ; no natural philosophy without an interpretation of nature that perfects itself according to the standard of experience. From every one of these as so many points of view Bacon may be characterised, for each gives an essential characteristic of his philosophy. He aims at the culture of humanity by a skilful application of natural science; he seeks to attain natural science by a right use of experience. By a correct method he would convert experience into science; by application in the form of invention, DEVOTION TO THE CAUSE OF SCIENCE. 63 he would convert science into art ; and this he would convert into a practical and general civilisation, designed for the whole race of man. What single name will suffice adequately to denote such a mind? By connecting his points of view in such logical order, Bacon becomes a great thinker. By opening the widest prospects into the realm of science, and into the whole sphere of human civilisation, from these points of view, by indicating goals and setting up problems in every direction, so that his system is nowhere brought to a conclusion and dogmatically hedged | round, the great thinker becomes an epoch-making = thinker. For it is the peculiarity of epoch-making gainds that they are open to the future. Bacon designed no finished system, but a living work, that should be continued in the progress of time. He sowed the seed for a future crop, which was to ripen slowly, and not to attain its perfection till centuries had elapsed. Bacon was well aware of this; he was satisfied to be the sower, and to begin a work which time alone could complete. This feeling with regard to himself was neither more nor less than a correct consciousness of his cause. At the conclusion of his preface to the “ Novum Organum ”* he says thus:— «Of our- * More cofrectly, the general preface to the “ Instauratia Magna,”— J, O, 64 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. selves we say nothing; but for the matter which is treated, we desire that men should regard it not as an opinion, but as a work, and should be assured that we are laying the foundation not of any sect or theory, but of that which conduces to the use and dignity of man. Next, we desire that, laying aside their jealousies and prejudices, they may fairly consult their own common advantage, and having been rescued by us from the errors and obstacles of their road and furnished with our defence and assistance, they may themselves par- ticipate in the labours that yet remain. More- over, that they may be strong in hope, and not imagine that our Instauratio is something infinite and beyond the reach of man, when it is really an end and legitimate termination to infinite error, and is so far mindful of the mortal lot of man that it does not hope to accomplish its work within the period of a single life, but leaves this to succeeding times; when, moreover, it does not arrogantly search for science in the narrow cells of human wit, but humbly in the greater world.”* In the * «De nobis ipsis silemus: de re autem que agitur petimus, ut homines eam non opinionem, sed opus esse cogitent, ac pro certo habeant, non secte nos alicujus aut placiti sed utilitatis et amplitudinis humanz fundamenta moliri. Deinde ut suis com- modis squi, exutis opinionum zelis et prejudiciis, in commune consulant, ac ab erroribus viarum atque impedimentis, nostris presidiis et auxillis, liberati et muniti laborum qui restant et DEGREES OF HUMAN AMBITION. 65 same spirit is the following passage, which occurs towards the end of the first book of the “ Novum Organum:”— “ It will not be amiss to distinguish three kinds, and, as it were, degrees of human ambition ; first, that of those who desire to enlarge their own power in their country, which is a vulgar and degenerate kind; next, that of those who strive to enlarge the power and dominion of their country among the human race, which is certainly more dignified, but no less covetous. But if one should endeavour to renew and enlarge the power and dominion of the human race itself over the universe, this ambition (if so it may be called) is, beyond a doubt, more sane and noble than the other two. Now the dominion of men over things depends alone on arts and sciences; for nature is only governed by obeying her,”* ipsi in partem veniant. Preeterea ut bene sperent, neque Instau- rationem nostram, ut quiddam infinitum et ultra mortale fingant et animo concipiant ; quum revera sit infiniti erroris finis et terminus legitimus ; mortalitatis autem et humanitatis non sit immemor ; quum rem non intra unius etatis curriculum omnino perfici posse confidat sed successioni destinet; denique scientias non per arrogantiam in humani ingenii cellulis, sed submisse in mundo majore queerat.” * “Preeterea, non abs re fuerit, tria hominum ambitionis genera et quasi gradus distinguere. Primum eorum, qui propriam po- tentiam in patria sua amplificare cupiunt ; quod genus vulgare est et degener. Secundum eorum, qui patrie potentiam et imperium inter humanum genus amplificare nituntur ; illud plus certe habet dignitatis, cupiditatis haud minus. Quod si quis K tot, | Vitae vppuded t — 66 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM., It is obvious that human culture depends upon experience, and the latter upon natural science in , the sense of an interpretation of nature. The question remains: How does experience become natural science? For at first it is nothing but a perception of single facts, a collecting together of manifold instances, an enumeration of the things perceived, and their properties; and the experi- ence of common minds scarcely ever rises above this ordinary level. By what means, then, does ordinary experience become scientific (and thus, consequently, inventive) experience? By what means does * Natural History ” (thus, with Bacon, we designate the narration of particulars) become Natural Science ?—how does historia naturalis become scientia naturalis? By what means does the description of nature (descriptio nature) be- come the interpretation of nature (interpretatio nature)? To these questions we are brought back by the problem which Bacon negatively proposes in the first book of the ‘* Novum Orga- num,” and positively solves in the second.* humani generis ipsius potentiam et imperium in rerum univer- sitatem instaurare et amplificare conetur, ea proculdubio ambitio (si modo ita vocanda sit) reliquis et sanior est et augustior. Hominis autem imperium in res, in solis artibus et scientiis ponitur. Nature enim non imperatur, nisi parendo.”— Nov, Urq. I, 329. * Bacon himself calls the first part of his “ Novum Organum” THE “IDOLS.” 67 I. Tue Ipots. Nature is to be interpreted like a book. The best interpretation is that which explains an author out of himself, and imputes to him no other sense than his own. The reader should not force his own sense upon the author, as he will thus render a correct understanding im- possible, and arrive at an imaginary interpretation, which, in truth, is none at all. As the reader who makes his comments is to the book, so should human experience be with regard to nature. Ac- ‘cording to Bacon, science is the edifice of the world in the human mind ; hence he calls it a temple after the example of the world. The understanding should copy nature, and nothing but nature, without idealising her, without abridging her; it should add nothing of itself, neither take away nor overlook anything belong- ing to the object, under the misleading influence of a childish and effeminate disgust at that which is foolishly termed mean or filthy." It should copy nature by imitating her details, and not from “ Pars destruens.” It is intended to refute adverse views, and to cleanse the human mind, like a threshing-floor, that this may be rendered capable and susceptible of a new kind of knowledge. Compare “ Noy, Org.” I. 115.—Author’s note. * Compare “ Noy. Org.” I. 120. F 2 CR. 68 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. pelio its own authority sketch a picture without caring for the original. Such a self-created picture is ms Fs Ky ted OS > not taken from the nature of things, but is antic?- pated by the human understanding. Considered in relation to the understanding, it is an antictpatio mentis; considered in relation to nature, it is an anticipatio nature ; compared with the original external to ourselves, it 1s no true copy, but a mere empty unreal image, that has no existence save in our own fancy ;—a creation of the brain (Hirngespinnst) or “ Idol.” Hence the first negative condition, without which a knowledge of nature is altogether impossible, is that idols may not be set in the place of real things — that in no case may there be an anticipatio mentis. Nothing should be anticipated, but all should be experienced, that is, derived from the things themselves. There should be no general con- ceptions (Begriffe) that are not preceded by actual observations; no judgments that are not preceded by actual experience; no anticipatio mentis, but only an interpretatio nature.* “ For the sake of distinction,” says Bacon, “we are wont to call human reasoning, as applied to nature, the anticipation of nature, because it is rash and premature; but that which is properly * Compare “ Nov. Org.,” pref. (towards the end). THE “IDOLS.” 69 deduced from things, the interpretation of nature.” * Here Bacon discovers the fundamental defect of all the science that has preceded him. Nature, instead of being interpreted, has been anticipated, inasmuch as explanations have been based either upon preconceived notions, or upon too scanty experience. Either the experience was made under the influence of an anticipatio mentis, or is interrupted by such an anticipation; in both cases something is assumed which has been in- sufficiently proved or not proved at all by experience. Thus there has been no correct and penetrating knowledge of nature, and thus orderly and deliberate invention has been im- possible. Invention has been left to chance ; — hence its excessive rarity; and science has re- mained occupied with idle speculations ; — hence its sterility. A want of experience, or a too credulous experience, lies at the foundation of all these deficiencies. The human understanding must henceforward become the perfectly pure and willing organ of experience. It must first get rid of all those notions, which it has deduced from its own * “Rationem humanam qua utimur ad naturam, Anticipa- tiones Nature (quia res temeraria est et prematura), at illam rationem que debitis modis elicitur a rebus, Interpretationem Nature, docendi gratia vocare consuevimus.”—Nov. Org. I. 26. Compare also to 33, inclusive. a F3 pn Prhne , “ 70 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. ‘p~*mature, not from that of things. These notions Aagpt are not found, but anticipated. Such “ Idols” belong to human nature, either as a natural or an historical inheritance. The natural idols are the peculiarities of the human species or of par- ticular individuals; and thus comprise errors common to the whole race (¢dola tribus), and accidental individual errors (idola specus). The historical idols depend upon manners, usages, and customs, such as arise from -the inter- course between man and man (7dola fori), or upon general traditions which on the great the- atre of humanity are handed down from gene- ration to generation (idola theatri). These idols obscure the human understanding, and hide from it the face of nature; they must be discarded for ever on the very threshold of science. “ The idols and false notions which have hitherto oc- cupied the human understanding and are deeply rooted in it, not only so beset the minds of men that the access of truth is rendered difficult, but even when access is given they will again meet and trouble us in the very restoration of the sciences; unless men, being forewarned, guard themselves as much as possible against them.” * * “ Tdola et notiones falsee quee intellectum humanum jam oc- cuparunt atque in eo alte herent, non solum mentes hominum ita obsident ut veritati aditus difficilis pateat ; sed etiam dato et ENUMERATION OF IDOLS. 71 The “idols,” according to Bacon, are the “ duties of omission” * in the world of science. They re- semble ignes futui, which the traveller ought to know in order to avoid them. Bacon would make us acquainted with these ignes fatui of science, that direct us from the true path of we f experience; therefore he treats first of the de- lusions, then of the method of knowledge. Whoever seeks real copies of things must beware of false semblances, just as the logical thinker must be on his guard against sophisms. ‘ The doctrine of “Idols,” says Bacon, “bears to the interpretation of nature a relation similar to that which the doctrine of sophisms bears to ordinary dialectic.” ¢ Il. Tue Bacontan Scepticism. BACON AND DESCARTES, To oppose idols and prejudices, whencesoever they may come, science begins with doubt —with concesso aditu, illa rursus in ipsa instauratione scientiarum occurrent et molesta erunt, nisi homines premoniti adversus ea se quantum fieri potest muniant.”—NVov. Org. I. 38. For the doctrine of “Idols,” compare the following Aphorisms to 68. inclusive. * “ Unterlassungspflichten.” t “Doetrina enim de Idolis similiter se habet ad Interpreta- tionem Nature, sicut doctrina de Sophisticis Elenchis ad Dia- lecticam yulgerem.”—WNov. Org. I. 40. Fr4 oly. av & 72 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. -_ is “utter uncertainty. Doubt is the starting-point, i m e not the goal of science; the goal is certain and well-grounded knowledge. Science, according to Bacon, should begin with “ Acatalepsia,” to ter- minate in “ Kueatalepsia.” The Baconian doubt seeks to shake not the foundations, but only | the false foundations of science, that a firm edifice after the pattern of the world may be raised in the human mind. Bacon agrees with the sceptics in his starting-point, not in his result. The views of those who adhered to Acatalepsia and our own method agree, to some extent, at the commencement; but in the end they differ im- mensely, and are completely opposed to each other. For the sceptics roundly assert that nothing can be known at all; we, that only a small part of nature can be known by the method now in use. They proceed next to destroy the au- thority of the senses and the understanding, for which we, on the contrary, invent and sup- 99 & ply assistance. And in the same spirit Bacon declares, towards the end of the first book of * «Ratio eorum qui acatalepsiam tenuerunt, et via nostra, | initiis suis quodammodo consentiunt ; exitu immensum disjun- guntur et opponuntur. Illi enim nihil sciri posse simpliciter asserunt ; nos non multum sciri posse in natura, ea que nunc in usu est via: verum illi exinde authoritatem sensus et intel- lectus destruunt ; nos auxilia iisdem excogitamus et submini- stramus.”—Nov. Org. I. 37. With respect to Bacon’s rela- tion to the Ancient Sceptics, compare the “ Scala Intellectus,” ACATALEPSIA AND EUCATALEPSIA, 73 the “ Noyum Organum:” “We do not con- template and propose Acatalepsia, but Euca- talepsia; for we do not derogate from, but assist the senses; and we do not despise, but direct the understanding. And it is better to know what is necessary, and at the same time to think that we do not know it thoroughly, than to think that we know thoroughly, and at the same time to know nothing of that which is required.” * Hence we may compare the Baconian doubt with the Cartesian; for these two, by effecting the revival of philosophy, divide the epoch of that revival between them. Both of them have the same origin and the same tendency, both have the same goal before them, and are actuated by the same internal conviction, that all the knowledge hitherto acquired is but uncertain, and that a new kind of knowledge is required. The cause of science must once more be under- taken from its very commencement; the work of the understanding must be performed anew. Thus alike think Bacon and Descartes. Therefore, by means of doubt, they withhold their assent from * “Nos vero non Acatalepsiam, sed Eucatalepsiam meditamur et proponimus; sensui enim non derogamus, sed ministramus ; et intellectum non contemnimus, sed regimus, Atque melius est scire quantum Opus sit et tamen nos non penitus scire pu- tare, quam penitus scire nos putare, et tamen nil eorum aac opus est scire.” — Nov. Org. I. 126. .) 74 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. uw VeNocartig oa the knowledge that has hitherto been deemed Pa th lath owt Cf. : a : vitllet jthe reformatory kind; it is a purification of the unquestionable, in order to obtain a clear field © for their labour of renovation. Their doubt is of _ (> understanding, with a view to a perfect renewal ytodhevcof science. But now, what is to be effected by = “\ the understanding thus purified, and therefore, in ““<'“ the first instance, vacant? Here the two re- formers of science part from each other in the opposite directions that are followed by after ages; here, from a common stock, spring the two trunks of modern philosophy. Descartes says, the pure understanding must be left wholly to itself, that from itself alone it may derive all its judgments. Bacon on the other hand de- clares, in the very preface to the “ Novum Or- ganum:” “ The only remaining hope and salva- tion is to begin over again the whole work of the mind, so that from the very first the mind may not be trusted to itself, but continually directed.”* The common root of modern philosophy is the doubt which is alike Baconian and Cartesian. : From this doubt springs the pure intellect, which | is left to itself by Descartes; while, on the other hand, it is fastened by Bacon to the leading- strings of nature. From these different, and, we * « Restat unica salus ac sanitas, ut opus universum mentis de integro resumatur ; ac mens, jam ab ipso principio, nullo modo sibi permittatur, sed perpetuo regatur.”—Vov. Org., pref. BACON AND DESCARTES. 75 may say, opposite dispositions of the philosophical understanding, arise the different directions taken by modern philosophy in the progress of its de- velopment. One series follows the self-sufficient _ intellect of Descartes, the other the intellect in the leading-strings of nature, to which it has been attached by Bacon. The representatives of the | former tendency are necessarily metaphysicians and idealists; those of the latter (necessarily — likewise) are empiricists and sensualists. The | Cartesian soil could not do otherwise than bring | forth a Spinoza and a Leibnitz; the Baconian naturally produced a Hobbes and a Locke, Leibnitz originates the German, Locke the An- glo-Gallic enlightenment (Aufkidrung), both of which lead to a new epoch in philosophy, in which they are merged at last. However, we need not here follow this yet distant prospect. We return to that doubt by means of which Bacon and Descartes purify the understanding from all prejudices. The understanding so puri- fied is directed by Descartes to itself, by Bacon to nature; the former makes it at once self- dependent, the latter makes it completely de- pendent on nature; or, to express ourselves figuratively, the pure understanding, just newly born, is at once matured to manhood with Des- cartes ; while with Bacon it is first in a state of childhood, and is treated asa child. This treat- 76 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. ment is less bold, but more judicious, because more conformable to nature. Bacon treats the understanding like a trainer; the child ought to grow and develop itself gradually. In a child-. like mind, which stands open, without reserve or prejudice, to the impressions of the world, must science be renewed, for thus it literally becomes _ once more young. According to the Baconian philosophy, the human understanding has a_ Natural History; while, according to the Car- . tesian, it is alike devoid of history and nature.*_ Bacon bids science meet the “Idols” with annihilating doubt, but nature with pure sus- ceptibility | (Empfanglichkeit). The human un- derstanding must resign itself wholly to nature with child-like confidence, that it may really feel domesticated with nature. Bacon loves to com- pare the dominion of man, which consists in knowledge, with the kingdom of Heaven, of which the Bible says: — ‘‘ Except ye become as little children, ye shall not enter into the kingdom of Heaven.” “ The idols of every kind,” says Bacon, “ must be abjured and renounced with a firm and solemn resolution, and the understanding must be wholly freed and cleared from them, that the access to the kingdom of man, which is * “ Natur- und Geschichtslos.” t Or “receptivity."—J. O. BACON AND DESCARTES. 77 founded in science, may be same as that to the kingdom of Heaven, where no entrance is possible, save by assuming the character of children.” * II. Tae Exrermentarisina Perception. In the spirit of Bacon, we may designate that view of things as alone correct which remains to us after the removal of all idols. These, Idols are the peculiarities of human nature and of individuals, the conventionalities of social intercourse, and the authorities confirmed by history. All these varieties may incontestibly have their value in their proper place, but they have nothing in common with the nature and quality of things, and therefore our observation of things ought not to be influenced by them. It is only with respect to science, which they should not affect, that they are idols. Of the classes above enumerated we omit that of individual peculiarity, as leading too much into the obscure and indefinite. The others are more manifestly * “Que omnia (idola) constanti et solenni decreto sunt ab- neganda et renuncianda, et intellectus ab iis omnino liberandus est et expurgandus; ut non alius fere sit aditus ad regnum hominis, quod fundatur in scientiis, quam ad regnum ccelorum, » in quod, nisi sub persona infantis, intrare non datur.?— Nov, Org. I. 68. - shee us 4 te é + 9 Or LAE AAU pln one bvees $ M ae onek Bont - é 78 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. and generally important; they are, therefore, worthy of a clear and accurate description.* 1, CONVICTION OPPOSED TO AUTHORITY. What results from our contemplation of things after the removal of all the systems and traditions supported by historical authority (édola theatri)? On authority, things are considered not as they appear to ourselves, but as they appear to public opinion, which clothes itself with the dignity of a traditional religion or philosophy. Thus they are contemplated without any judgment or ex- perience of our own. On the other hand, our contemplation, when it becomes independent, is converted into autopsy, into observation actually made by ourselves, so that we no longer take upon trust and repeat that which is said or reputed true by others, but only adhere, by virtue of our own convictions, to that which we have ourselves perceived and experienced. Thus, in astronomy, for example, the Ptolemzan system, * In the omission of the “Idola specus,” and in the order in which we have ranged the three other Idols, we have followed not our own choice, but the Baconian prescription, Bacon him- self calls the negative part of his logic (that is to say, the refu- tation of the Idols) “triplex,” and designates the three parts : « redargutio philosophiarum ” (idola theatri), “red. demonstra- tionum ” (id. fori), and “red. rationis humane nature (id. tri- bus).—Vide the tract “Partis instaurationis secunda delineatio.” IDOLS OF THE THEATRE. 79 supported by a certain interpretation of Scripture, was an “ Idolum theatri,” which science, in the person of Copernicus, solemnly and for ever aban- doned. Here for the first time she has used her own faculties in observing, with perfect indepen- dence, whether the sun really moves and the earth really stands still, and arrives at a result opposed to the belief entertained by public opinion. The exclusion from science of the “ Idola theatri,” as decisive grounds, amounts to a declaration that science is independent of all belief based on authority, and that man is to be referred to his own convictions alone. 2. REAL OPPOSED TO VERBAL KNOWLEDGE, After the remoyal of the first class of idols, nothing remains but a personal acquaintance with the things themselves. But now in most cases we fancy that we know things, without having seriously learned to know them. We think we are certain as to their value, because we possess the symbols of it, and circulate them with facility, These symbols are names or words, which we BAR. sooner than the nature of the things themselves, and with the assistance of which men communicate their notions to each other. Accustomed from childhood to put words in the place of things, ey 80 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. and with these words to be perfectly intelligible to everybody, we involuntarily take them, mere signs as they are, for the things signified,—the nominal for the real value. Words are, as it were, the current coin, by means of which we put forth and take in our notions of things; they constitute, like money in trade, not the real and natural, but the conventional value of things, as ‘settled by the relations of human intercourse. We must not take this market-price for the thing itself, with respect to which it is completely extrinsic and indifferent. So little are words guided by the nature of things, that (for instance), in common parlance*, the sun still moves round the earth, though in truth this never was the case, and though we have long been convinced of. the contrary. Words do not say what things are, but what they denote to us; they represent our own notions, and generally are as uncertain as_ our notions are obscure. Because words and the. usages of language designate things not as they are in their own nature, but as they are considered in the intercourse between man and man, Bacon reckons the delusion, through which we cling to words, and fancy we grasp the things them- * As in expressions that refer to the rising or setting of the sun.—J. O. IDOLS OF THE TRIBE. 81 selves, among the Idola Fori.* Hence Bacon — * faata ve beh loves so much to oppose the wisdom of words to “Pp the knowledge of things; an opposition that fur~ a nished a watchword to hissuccessors. His remarks on the subject of words, while treating of the Idola Fori, contain a brief programme of all the inquiries about language that have been made in accordance with his views. In these investigations both the ** Forum ” itself and the “ Idols” play their part: the Forum, because language appears as~a result of human invention, that is to say, a mere arbi- trary piece of bungling workmanship; the Idols, because words represent general conceptions,-and . therefore unreal notions. 3. NATURAL ANALOGY OPPOSED TO HUMAN ANALOGY. The Idola Theatri consist in this: that we take things not as they appear to ourselves, but as they are declared to be on the authority of another; that we see them with the eyes of others instead of our own. The Idola Fori consist in this: that we take things not as they are, but as they appear to us through the medium of human intercourse. What view of things is left after the removal of the Idola Fori? Our own knowledge is directed from the signs to the things signified, * Compare Noy. Org. 59, 60. G +t 82 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. and these can only be learned by our own per- ception and investigation. But then, is even our own perception correct ? Are things really what we take them to be,—as they are reflected in our senses? Are the sen- sible impressions true copies of things themselves —an expression corresponding to their nature, and not rather an expression corresponding to our own? Our own perception and conception of things is, as it were, a translation of them from physical into human nature, from the universe into our own individuality; a translation in which the original loses its own peculiarity, and arbi- trarily assumes an human peculiarity in its stead. Thus, even in our own immediate perception of things,—apart from the doctrines enforced by authority and the notions current in social inter- course —there is something foreign to the things themselves ; something superadded by us; some- thing that lies in the conditions of our nature, so that we fail to make true copies of things, and produce distorted images instead. Our own notion of nature presents delusive phantoms to. our_gaze, deceives us with false representations. These are, to use Bacon’s words, the Jdola Tribus, which are the most potent of all, for they govern the entire human race; and their government is the hardest to overthrow, inasmuch as they have been IDOLS OF THE TRIBE. a nist founded not by historical authority in the course ff. | of time, but by nature itself. The human soul is, indeed, a mirror of things, but this mirror is so cut by nature that, while it reflects things, it at+ as Rs the same time alters them, and does not exhibit [Give one without blending with it an human element, aes a —without, by a certain magic, transferring it we into something human. What is there in common between things themselves and human forms ? What has the sun to do with the fact that to the eyes of an inhabitant of the earth he appears to move? This is an illusion, the cause of which lies not in the motion of the sun, but in our own eyes, to which our own planet is the point of view. If I assert that the sun moves, because we } are taught so by Ptolemy, I judge by an Jdolum Theatri. If I make the same assertion, on the ground that everybody says so likewise, I judge by an Idolum Fori. If I say: “ The sun moves, because I see it move with my own eyes,” I. judge by an Idolum Tribus. I feel, for instance,’ the warmth of the water, and determine the degree of warmth by my. sensations. But the same water appears first cold and a few mo- ments afterwards warm, without any change having taken place in the degree of its warmth. The warmth of my body has changed, and this body when heated feels the water cold, when G2 84. FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. cooled feels the water warm. Thus is it with all our perceptions,—with our entire contem- plation of things. We measure and judge them by our own standard, we view them from a point that lies in our own nature, which is indeed the nearest and most natural as far as we are concerned, but with respect to the things is per- fectly foreign and indifferent. We apprehend \them not as they are in themselves, but as they stand in relation to us; not according to their f , i ° vprees own analogy, but according to ours; or to use the Tie V »- Baconian language, we consider things ex analogia 2OV “4 hominis, not ex analogia univers. Under this m5 8 formula the Idola Tribus may best be noted. “‘ These Idols,” says Bacon, “are founded in human nature itself,—in the very tribe or race of men. It is falsely asserted that human sense is the standard of things, since, on the contrary, all the perceptions both of the senses and of the mind are according to the analogy of man, not that of the universe, and the human intellect is like an uneven mirror to the rays of things, — blending its own nature with the nature of the object, so as to distort and disfigure the latter.”* * “Tdola Tribus sunt fandata in ipsa natura humana, atque in ipsa tribu seu gente hominum. Falso enim asseritur, sensum humanum esse mensuram rerum; quin contra, omnes percep- tiones tam sensus quam mentis sunt ex analogia hominis, non SPINOZA AND BACON. 85 This passage is mentioned in very contemptuous terms by Spinoza in his letter to Oldenburg. He treats Bacon as a confused babbler, who talks at random about the cause of error and the nature of the mind. But, far from refuting Bacon, he does not clearly show the point that constitutes the utter difference between Bacon and himself, It is worth while to give prominence to this point, for there is manifestly a great deal in the passage above cited that Spinoza himself might have said. In the first place, Man is not the measure (or standard) of things: this proposition is in the very spirit of Spinoza. In the second place, all those notions are false that are formed according to the analogy of man, and not according to that of nature, and herein lies the ground of error, — Error consists in the inadequate representation of things: this sentence is no less Spinozistic. In the third place, all our representations, both sen- suous and logical, are according to human analogy, and therefore inadequate; the human understanding is by nature an inadequate mirror of things. In this third proposition alone lies that difference between the two that Spinoza should have shown more clearly. For, according to him, truth is naturally ex analogia universi, Estque intellectus humanus instar speculi inequalis ad radios rerum, qui suam naturam nature rerum immiscet, eamque distorquet et inficit.”—Vov, Org. I. 41. @ 3 86 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. immanent in the human mind, only it is, at first, veiled and obscured by inadequate (sensuous) ideas. Hence, with Spinoza, true knowledge solely consists in the clearing up of obscure ideas, in the emendation of the understanding. With him the understanding is corrected from its own resources; while, on the other hand, with Bacon it is brought to right knowledge by the leading- strings of nature through continued experience. This contrast between Spinoza and Bacon is the same that is to be found between Bacon and Descartes; between Locke and Leibnitz; between empiricism and idealism generally. That Spinoza will make no concession to his adversary, lies in the character of his point of view. Perhaps it was displeasing to him to find, from an opposite point of view, so much that was kmdred to his own thoughts ; perhaps this very affinity in Bacon especially revolted him. With him the will was a consequence of knowledge, and could never, therefore, be a ground of error. Now of Bacon he says: “ Whatever further causes he may as- sign to error are easily reducible to the one cause of Descartes, namely, that the human will is free and more comprehensive than the understanding ; or as Bacon himself (Aph. 49.) more confusedly expresses himself, because the understanding has not the quality of a dry light, but receives an CORRECTIONS FOR THE MIND. 87 infusion from the will.” This passage is not accurately quoted.* It stands thus: “The human understanding has not the quality of a dry light, but receives an infusion from the will and the passions, whence science is generated in accord- ance with the wish; for that which man desires should be true he the more readily believes.” Now what does Bacon say? That desire perplexes the understanding. And what says Spinoza? That desire is a perplexed understanding. In point of fact, the two propositions declare the same thing, namely, the perplexity of desire. 4, EXPERIMENT OPPOSED TO THE DELUSION OF THE SENSES, Sense and Instrument. What then remains for us, when the under- standing and the senses deceive us, and the human mind is by nature a deceptive mirror of things? The understanding and the senses must not be left as they are; they must be cultivated, corrected, assisted, that they may correspond to things; the magic mirror of the * More properly, the quotation is too abruptly terminated, t Vide Appendix A. G4 88 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. mind must be made smooth, and polished bright, that the speculum inequale may become a specu- lum equale. And how can this be effected ?— not by nature, but only by art. What is im- possible for the mere senses and the unassisted understanding, — namely, a correct perception of things, —is attainable both by senses and understanding with the aid of an instrument. Equipped with a fitting instrument, human perception becomes correct; without one it 1s fallacious. What is invisible or obscure to the naked eye, becomes visible and clear to the eye armed with a microscope or telescope. The human hand ean, indeed, feel the warmth of the water, but cannot arrive at a right judgment respecting it; for it feels its own warmth at the same time, and accordingly as this is greater or less than_ the warmth of the water, the latter appears cooler or warmer. The actual warmth of the water is only ascertained by the thermo- meter, which reveals to the eye what the hand is unable to perceive. We will call perception (Wahrnehmung), when aided by an instrument, “ observation” (Beobachtung); and the process by which we exhibit a natural phenomenon in its purity, without any heterogeneous element, an experiment. In this spirit, Bacon himself declares : ‘Neither the bare hand nor the understanding, ANTHROPOMORPHIC VIEW OF NATURE. 89 left to itself, can effect much; effects are produced by means of instruments and helps.”* And in another place: All true interpretation of nature consists in accurate experiments, whereby the senses pronounce judgment only upon the ex- periment, but the experiment upon the object itself, 5. EFFICIENT OPPOSED TO FINAL CAUSES. f However, not only in the nature of the senses, but also in that of the human understanding, are iliusive phantoms that destroy the true know- ledge of things. And there is one notion, espe- cially, that most easily and mischievously misleads. the human understanding, most effectually falsifies the interpretation of nature, and is the chief cause of the ignorance and sterility that has hitherto prevailed in science. We have a propensity to transfer to things our own nature and its attri- butes, thus accommodating things to ourselves, and not ourselves to things, and apprehending the phenomena of nature according to human analogy.. Thus we interpret nature falsely ; endowing her with human attributes, and conceiving her not * “Nec manus nuda nec intellectus sibi permissus multum valet ; instrumentis et auxiliis res perficitur.”—Nov. Org. I, 2. t “ Causalitat gegen Teleologie.” g Cans te’ ie a/ “a 7) gle 90 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. something physical, but something anthropo- morphic. It belongs to the very constitution «+g, Of our understanding to form generic ideas; and RAG ' “Ag ; 2' AH, f t rans 3. bikean 06 = ‘ek et 4 pwbag . to that of our will to act with certain ends in view. ‘These generic ideas and ends (or goals) are forms that belong essentially to man, but explain nothing in the nature of things. Never- theless, these very ideas that explain nothing have hitherto constituted the principles of what is called Natural Philosophy. Bacon reckons Final Causes among the Jdola Tribus, and in the region of physics finds them not only useless, but injurious. He deduces them in the following manner from the propensity of the human under- standing: “The human understanding, being restless and unable to halt or rest, ever presses forward, but in vain. ‘Thus it appears incon- ceivable that there is any final boundary to the world, but it always seems necessarily to occur to us that there must be something beyond. Nor, indeed, can we imagine how eternity has flowed down to the present day ; for the ordinary distinction of an infinity, a parte ante and a parte post, cannot hold good, inasmuch as it would necessarily follow that one infinity is greater than another, and also that infinity is wasting. away and verging toanend. There is a similar subtilty with regard to the infinite divisibility of TENDENCY TO SEEK FINAL CAUSES. 91 lines arising from the weakness of our own faculty of thought. But still greater mischief arises from this mental impotency in the discovery of causes. For though the greatest generalities in nature should be positive just as they are found, and in point of fact are not causable; nevertheless the ¥ human understanding, incapable of rest, seeks for ¥ something better known. Thus, however, whilst aiming at what is more remote, it falls back to | what is nearer, namely, to final causes, which clearly belong more to the nature of man than to that of the universe; and from this souxee philo- sophy has been marvellously corrupted. Indeed, it is the part of an inexperienced and shallow | philosopher to seek for causes in the greatest ,, generalities, and not to require a cause for sub- ‘ ordinate objects.” * * “Gliscit intellectus humanus, neque consistere aut acquiescere potis est, sed ulterius petit ; at frustra. Itaque incogitabile est ut sit aliquid extremum aut extimum mundi, sed semper quasi necessario occurrit ut sit aliquid ulterius : neque rursus cogitari potest quomodo externitas defluxerit ad hunc diem; cum dis- tinctio illa que recipi consuevit, quod sit infinitum a parte ante et a parte post, nullo modo constare possit ; quia inde sequeretur quod sit unum infinitum aiio infinito majus, atque ut con- sumatur infinitum, et vergat ad finitum. Similis est subtilitas de lineis semper divisibilibus, ex impotentia cogitationis. At majore cum pernicie intervenit hec impotentia mentis in inventione causarum ; nam cum maxime universalia in natura positiva esse debeant, quaemadmodum inveniuntur, neque sunt revera causa- bilia ; tamen intellectus humanus, nescius acquiescere, adhuc * 92 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. th PRM KH | | bly Bete By the idea of a final cause, metaphysics are a pdeyns distinguished from physics. An interpretation of hat A ~yature by final causes is a mixture of metaphysics with physics, which renders the latter confused and sterile. Sterility in a science is, to Bacon’s mind, something deplorable; and as he has proposed to free science from its wretched con- dition, he is bent upon clearing up perplexities, separating what has wrongly mixed, parting the heterogeneous. He would exhibit physics in all their purity, and therefore he assigns to meta- physics the forms and final causes that are of no service to physics. Physics are occupied not with the forms, but with the matter of things; they explain individual phenomena, are satisfied with secondary causes, with which they inter- pret everything in nature, and interpreting no- thing by final causes, leave the primary origin of | things to metaphysics. The efficient are, in fact, the physical causes. Thus, in his work “ De Augmentis Scientiarum,” Bacon designates the theory of final causes as a portion of meta- appetit notiora. Tum vero ad ulteriora tendens ad proximiora recidit, videlicet ad causas finales, que sunt plane ex natura hominis potius quam universi ; atque ex hoc fonte philosophiam miris modis corruperunt. Est autem esque imperiti et leviter philosophantis, in maxime universalibus causam requirere, ac in subordinatis et subalternis causa non desiderare.”—Vov. Org. I. 48. EVIL OF FINAL CAUSES. 93 physics that has hitherto not been overlooked, but assigned to a wrong department. “The > inquiry of final causes,” he says, “I am moved to report not as omitted, but as misplaced; and yet if it were but a fault in order, I could not speak of it, for order is matter of illustration, but pertaineth not to the substance of sciences. But this misplacing hath caused a deficience, or at least a great improficience in the sciences them- selves. For the handling of final causes, mixed with the rest in physical inquiries, hath inter- cepted the severe and diligent inquiry of all real and physical causes. . . . And therefore the natural philosophy of Democritus and some others _ (who did not suppose a mind or reason in_the power of things, but attributed the form thereof, able to maintain itself, to infinite essays or proofs of nature, which they term fortune,) seemeth to me, as far as I can judge by the recital and frag- ments which remain unto us, in particularities of physical causes, more real and better inquired than that of Aristotle or Plato.” * Thus, the position of Bacon among philoso- phical minds is determined. He would establish the dominion of man over nature, by means of * “ Advancement of Learning.” The parallel passage in “De Aug. Scient.” to which Dr, Fischer refers, will be found in lib. iii. cap. iy. 94 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. invention; he would arrive at invention by the interpretation of nature, without idols. Do not, in your view of things, allow yourself to be swayed by any authority or doctrine whatever, but observe for yourself. Learn to know things themselves; not through the medium of words, but as they are in reality, — not according to current notions, but as they are in nature. Make experiments and observations for yourself; but do not let your observations be affected by ana- logies drawn from the nature of man (analogia | hominis); do not be misled by the senses, which present you with illusions, nor by the hasty understanding that rapidly flies over details and involuntarily substitutes itself for the physical forces; that is to say, rest your observations upon experiment, set out with the exclusion of final causes from your interpretation of nature, nowhere seek for anything beyond the efficient causes of natural phenomena. Thus that which remains after the removal of all the idols, is experimentalising perception from the point of view taken by mechanical or physical causality. By this course alone can the human mind attain a real copy of nature, which according to Bacon is the true object. of science. ‘The world is not to be confined EXPERIMENT THE ONLY ROAD TO SCIENCE, 95 (as hitherto) within the straits of the intellect, but the intellect is to be enlarged to receive the image of the world, such as it is.” * * «“Neque enim arctandus est mundus ad angustias intellectus (quod adhuc factum est), sed expandendus intellectus et lax- andus ad mundi imaginem recipiendam, qualis invenitur.”—- Parasceve, IV. 96 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. CHAP. IV. TRUE INDUCTION AS THE METHOD OF EXPERIENCE. Tue only true and fruitful mode of contem- plating nature is experimentalising perception, directed solely to the efficient causes of things. The perception thus attained, after the removal of all Idols, —this perfectly objective view of things we will, with Bacon, call “pure experience ” (mera experientia). The end of experience is obvious enough ;—it proceeds from the facts of nature, and directs itself to their causes. A way, therefore, is to be found that will lead from one point to another,—not by a mere happy chance, but of necessity, —and this way is the method of experience. The first task it proposes is to ascer- tain facts, that is, to establish what really hap- pens, with the circumstances of the event, and thus to collect materials, which will form the elementary substance —as it were, the capital of science. Let us suppose this task — this guestio facti—performed to the greatest possible perfec- tion, and we have a series of cases, a collection of facts, which when they are once establishéd COMPARISON OF INSTANCES. 97 can at first merely be enumerated. Thus, the performance of the first task consists in the ; simple enumeration (enumeratio simplex) of per- ceived facts, which, properly arranged, consti- tute the description of nature or “ Natural History.” Now how from such a description do we get ascience of nature? How from this expe- rience do we obtain knowledge; or, what is the same thing, how do we ascend from the experienc. of facts to the experience of causes? There is no (zeal knowledge before the experience of causes, -w¥ e. r,as Bacon says: “To know truly is to know from causes.”* How then am I to learn the causes, the effective conditions, on which the phenomenon in question is to be found? I. Tue CoMPARISON OF SEVERAL INSTANCES. Every natural phenomenon is presented to me | under certain conditions. ‘The point therefore is, among the various data to ascertain those that | are absolutely necessary and essential to the phe- _ nomenon in question ; so that it would not be possible without them, ‘‘ How shall I find the essential conditions ?”—that is the question, and | the answer is: ‘‘ By setting aside whatever is Sacestiet or contingent.” The residue of the * “Recte ponitur ; vere scire esse per causas scire.”— lov. Org. Lib. IL. Aph. 2. H 98 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. data, after this operation, will manifestly consist of those that are essential and true. As the necessary conditions in all instances consist of the data that are left after this deduction, Bacon \ terms these the “true difference” (differentia vera); which he further designates as the fountain of things, operative nature, the form of a given phenomenon.* As the true contemplation of things is the perception of them by man after the removal of all idols, the true conditions of a pheno- menon are those that remain after the deduction of contingencies. Now arises the question: “ How shall I know what is contingent?” The dis- covery of contingencies, and the separation of them from the other data, is the real purpose and. aim of the Baconian experience. If this problem is solved, we have arrived at the discernment of the essential conditions of a phenomenon, conse- quently at the knowledge of the natural law itself, or the interpretatio nature. There is only one way of obtaining the solution, viz., the comparison of a number of similar instances. This comparison must be of a two- fold kind. In the first place we should compare several instances in which the same phenomenon * “Date autem nature Formam, sive differentiam veram, sive naturam naturantem, sive fontem emanationis invenire, opus et intentio est Humane Scientiz.”—Vov. Org. I. 1. SEPARATION OF CONTINGENCIES, 99 (heat, for instance) occurs under various condi- tions, then with these instargpes we should com- pare others, where, under similar conditions, the same phenomenon does noé occur. The former instances, which Bacon calls “ positive” (instan- tie positive sive convenientes) are similar with respect to the phenomenon under consideration ; the latter, which he calls “negative” (enstantie negative vel contradictive) are similar with respect to the conditions. What is required, therefore, is a comparison of the positive instances with each other, and also with the negative. Thus if, for instance, heat is the phenomenon under consideration, the sun that gives warmth is a positive instance; while, on the other hand, the moon and stars that give no warmth are negative. From the comparison of these it is clear that a celestial luminary is by no means an essential condition of light.* Those conditions alone are necessary that are connected with the phenomenon in every instance ; those that are not are merely contingent. There is heat connected with phenomena of light, but there is also heat without light, and light without heat ; hence light is not an essential factor of heat.t * Or rather, light is not a necessary consequence of a celes- tial luminary.—J. O. Tt Compare Nov. Org. II. 11—20. H 2 190 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. hadi on mali Thus, by accurate and frequent comparison, : on 9 fave non-essential conditions are detected, and by their ato as, exclusion (reectio) the essential conditions are - wi : attained. Thus experience proceeds from fact to a fact till it arrives at a law—from the singular to high oe : the universal. It confirms fact by experiment; m= discovers, by a fitting comparison of facts, the universal law, principle, or axiom by which the ‘operation of nature is guided. Thus, to speak in '\the manner of Bacon, experience ascends from the experiment to the axiom. This is the me- }thod of Induction, which Bacon therefore calls ‘the true key to natural philosophy. To deduce ‘axioms from experiments, ‘‘ we must first prepare a complete and accurate natural and experimental history. This constitutes our foundation, for we must not imagine or invent, but discover the operations of nature. But natural and expe- rimental history is so varied and diffuse in its material that it confounds and distracts the human understanding, unless it be fixed and exhibited in due order. ‘Therefore tables and co-ordinations of instances must be framed in such a manner and order that the understanding may be able to act upon them. Even when this is done, the understanding, left to itself and its own operation, is incompetent and unfit to form axioms, without direction and support. Hence we must, in the NEGATIVE INSTANCES. 101 third place, apply a true and legitimate Induction, which is the very key of interpretation.”* Il. Tue Imrvort or NEGATIVE INSTANCES. CRITICAL EXPERIENCE. Bacon calls his own induction “ legitimate” and “true” to distinguish it from another that is neither legitimate nor true, that proceeds without rule, and arrives at false results. Experience and induction are in themselves so far from new, that, on the contrary, they form the daily sus- tenance of our knowledge. Every day makes an addition to our experience; and at last, by summing up our daily experiences, we arrive at a total result, which has, for us, the force of an axiom. ‘This inference of a supposed axiom from a fact is also of the inductive kind; and by means * “Primo enim paranda est Historia Naturalis et Experi- mentalis, sufficiens et bona ; quod fundamentum rei est; neque enim fingendum aut excogitandum, sed inveniendum, quid natura faciat aut ferat. Historia vero Naturalis et Experi- mentalis tam varia est et sparsa, ut intellectum confundat et disgreget, nisi sistatur et compareat ordine idoneo. Itaque formandz sunt Tabulze et Coordinationes Instantiarum, tali modo et instructione ut in eas agere possit intellectus. Id quoque licet fiat, tamen intellectus sibi permissus et sponte movens inecompetens est et inhabilis ad opificium axiomatum, nisi regatur et muniatur. Itaque tertio, adhibenda est Induc- tio legitima et vera, que ipsa Clavis est Interpretationis.”— Nov. Org. II. 10, H 3 102 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. LAA Oe ag of this sort of induction is found that wisdom of . ,, ordinary life of which we have an instance in the ey * weather-wisdom” of a peasant. But just in ania the same manner we are convinced every day -S. uli that our experiences thus formed are insecure,— bet ‘hat our inferences are incorrect. A new expe- alee rience, on which we did not reckon in summing up those preceding, shows that our rule was false; and a single instance is sufficient to refute the validity of a supposed law. If that which, according to our rule, ought to occur, fails to occur on one occasion only, this is a proof that ithe rule was no better than an “idol.” Sucha isingle case, in opposition toa rule, is a negative — ‘instance. And in the course of our ordinary ex- perience we constantly meet with such negative instances that annihilate the results based upon our previous experience, and, on that account, re- ceived by us with implicit faith. Rules for the weather are constantly made ridiculous by nega- tive instances; and ordinary experience is not, more certain than the almanac. Experience does not become certain till it has no more to appre- hend from negative instances; till its results are no longer exposed to the risk of being over- thrown every moment by some unexpected occur- rence; till, in a word, there are no unforeseen cases by which it can be opposed. How is this NEGATIVE INSTANCES. 103 security to be attained? In one way alone. Experience must, as far as it is possible, foresee , every case; must guard itself betimes against the. danger of negative instances, by taking them into consideration ; nay, before it draws an inference it must itself seek for the negative instances, that. these may not afterwards rise in opposition and, overthrow premature results. To distinguish this’ course from that of ordinary experience, Bacon calls it “ methodical ;” to distinguish it from or- dinary induction, he calls it “true.” An expe- rience can only be refuted by the testimony of opposing facts ; and if there is no fact left to bear Witness against it, it is altogether irrefutable, — stands perfectly firm. The only defence which experience can provide against such a testimony is by seeking it out, and eliminating it, before a final decision is made. As in a lawsuit it should, as it were, confront the positive. with the negative instances, and after the hearing pronounce a sentence, according to the approved maxim of every fair judge: Audiatur et altera pars ! Negative instances render experience difficult, and, in a sciegtific sense, legitimate. With- out them it is easy and uncritical. Thus Bacon assigns the highest importance to negative instances ; they are with him the criterion of em- pirical truth, -— its only voucher. We can vouch | H 4 104 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. (£4 . for atruth when it cannot be contradicted ; we can tet ®§ vouch for empirical truth when experience does not sonal pronounceany one of its judgments, without taking into consideration, elucidating and solving all con- tradictory cases. This can only be effected by means of negative instances, which compel expe- rience to pause at every step, and provide it with a clue by which it slowly and surely approaches a fixed goal, instead of prematurely hurrying towards one that is merely illusive. Thus is ex- perience placed beyond the reach of contradiction. «J think,” says Bacon, “that a form of in- duction should be introduced, which from certain instances should draw general conclusions, so that the impossibility of finding a contrary in- stance might be clearly proved.”* By an unre- mitting comparison of positive with negative in- stances, necessary conditions are separated from contingencies. Hence Bacon calls the com- parative understanding, the “ divine fire” by which nature is sifted, and the laws of her pheno- mena are brought to light. “A solution and separation of nature must be effected, not indeed * * “Visum est ei talem inductionis formam introduci, que ex aliquibus generaliter concludat ; ita ut instantiam contradic- toriam inveniri non posse demonstretur.”—Cogitata et Visa. It is scarcely necessary to state that throughout this treatise Bacon speaks of himself in the third person.—J. O. USE OF DOUBT. 105 by fire, but by the understanding, which is, as it were, a divine fire.”* Man is only per- mitted to proceed first by negatives, and then to arrive at affirmatives, after every kind of ex- clusion.” ¢ We have already seen how the Baconian science takes its origin from doubt, which leaves it no- thing but pure experience. It does not adhere to doubt like the sceptics, but strives after certain knowledge, though still taking doubt as a con- stant guide through all its investigations, and concluding none till this guide has been heard and satisfied. That first doubt, which precedes all science, makes this science purely empirical. The second doubt, that accompanies science at every step, renders experience critical. Without the first, experience, even in its first origin, would be encumbered with idols, and never attain a clear result; without the second, it would grasp idols instead of truths in its path, and thus become credulous and superstitious. Against this con- tingency it is protected by unremitting doubt, by * “Nature facienda est prorsus solutio et separatio, non per ignem certe, sed per mentem, tanquam ignem divinum.”—Vov. Org. Il. 16. ¢ “(Homini) tantum conceditur, procedere primo per nega- tivas et postremo loco desinere in affirmativas post omnimodam exclusionem,”—Vov. Org. IL 15. 106 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. the critical understanding, that against every posi- tive instance invokes a negative. Whence, then, do credulity and superstition derive their origin ? Only from the want of critical understanding, — from the disregard of negative instances, — from an easy and indolent contentment with a few positive instances picked up at pleasure. If the negative instances had obtained a fair hearing, there would not have been so many rules about the weather; and the many marvels that have been ascribed to inexplicable and demoniac powers would never have been believed. Thus, for in- stance, we are told of somnambulists who predict / Oe the future. The credulous understanding is satisfied with one (perhaps doubtful) instance, spreads it about, becomes superstitious, and renders others superstitious likewise. The cri- tical understanding asks, Where are the som- nambulists who do not prophesy, or whose pre- dictions are not fulfilled? Without doubt they might be found if they were only sought; and one single negative instance would be sufficient to banish from the whole world a belief in the infallibility of such prophecies,—to convince the whole world that in these cases other powers are at work than the demoniac or the divine. If every belief of the kind that appeals to certain cases, to NEGATIVE INSTANCES. 107 certain experiences, were forced to undergo ex- perimentally the ordeal of negative instances, how few would endure the test! What would be- come of Swedenborg and Cagliostro? “It was well answered by him,” says Bacon, “ who, being shown in a temple the votive tablets of those who had escaped the peril of shipwreck, and being, moreover, pressed whether he would then acknow- ledge the power of the gods, asked where were the portraits of those who had perished after making their vows. The same may be said of nearly every kind of superstition, as that of astro- logy, dreams, omens, retributive judgments, and the like, in which men, delighted with vanities of the sort, observe the events when they are fulfilled, but neglect or pass them by, though much more numerous, whenever a failure occurs. But with much more subtilty does this evil in- sinuate itself into philosophy and the sciences, in which a maxim that has once been accepted infects and governs all others, though much more worthy of confidence. Besides, even if that eagerness and vanity, to which we have referred, did not exist, there is still this peculiar and per- petual error in the human mind, that it is swayed and excited more by affirmatives than by nega- tives; whereas it ought duly and regularly to regard both with impartiality; nay, in establish- 108 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. ing any true axiom there is greater force in the | negative than in the positive instance.”* For | manifestly that which is refuted by a single in- | stance cannot be proved by an hundred. ' The negative instances, of which Bacon would make methodical use, stand in his philosophy as a security against too credulous reliance on indi- vidual experience; against all hasty assumption ; in a word, against “idols.” They constitute, in the philosophical understanding, the spirit of contra- diction ; the logical goad of that “ enlightenment” (Aufklirung) that the successors of Bacon have diffused over the earth. The Anglo-Gallic “ en- lightenment,” in every case, directs this weapon * “Recte respondit ille, qui, cum suspensa tabula in templo ei monstraretur eorum qui vota solverant quod naufragii periculo elapsi sint, atque interrogando premeretur anne tum quidem deorum numen agnosceret, quesivit denuo, At ubi sint ill depicti qui post vota nuncupata perierint ? Eadem ratio est fere omnis superstitionis, ut in astrologicis, in somniis, ominibus, nemesibus, et hujusmodi; in quibus homines delectati hujus- modi vanitatibus advertunt eventus ubi implentur, ast ubi fal- lunt (licet multo frequentius) tamen negligunt et preetereunt. At longe subtilius serpit hoc malum in philosophiis et scientiis ; in quibus quod semel placuit reliqua (licet multo firmiora et potiora) inficit et in ordinem redigit. Quinetiam licet abfuerit ea quam diximus delectatio et vanitas, is tamen humano intel- lectui error est proprius et perpetuus, ut magis moveatur et excitetur affirmativis quam negativis ; cum rite et ordine equum se utrique praebere debeat; quin contra, in omni axiomate vero constituendo, major est vis instantiz negative.”—JVov. Org. I. 46. CRITICAL EXPERIENCE. 109 against the Idola Theatri, with which it con- tends, and batters down authorised systems by advancing facts in opposition; that is to say, negative instances. When Locke, for example, opposes the Cartesian theory of “ Innate Ideas,” by citing the cases of individuals who are des- titute of the ideas that have been called “ ine nate,” it is in a truly Baconian spirit that, while attacking the assumed doctrine, he appeals to the negative instance. And with this negative in- stance he is satisfied that he has completely re- futed Descartes. Mere experience will not guard us against idols, much less the unassisted understanding. Critical experience can alone defend science against illusion. For mere experience does not observe negative instances, but collects cases, and from them hastily derives axioms; while as for the unassisted under- standing, it derives its knowledge solely from itself, without observing any external instances at all. Thus neither attain true copies of things. On the other hand, critical experience combines the wealth of experience with the force of the understanding, thus avoiding the one-sidedness and consequently the errors of both. It collects by sifting, and is thus both experimental and in- tellectual; is a rational thinking experience. Here alone does Bacon find the salvation of science ; in 110 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. the union of reason and experience, while the de- plorable condition of science he attributes to their separation. ‘“ We think,” he says, “that we have established for ever a real and legitimate union between the empirical and rational faculties, whose morose and inauspicious divorces and repudiations have brought so much disturbance to the human family.” Thus does Bacon oppose his own point of view to that of the past, as new and more elevated, reconciling as it does the stubborn differences that have hitherto existed. This opposition of facul- ties was necessarily unfruitful in its results, and it is only from their union that a fruitful and in- ventive science can take its beginning. In that happily figurative language, which constitutes one of the great qualities of his style, Bacon com- pares mere experience to the ants, that can do nothing but collect; the unaided understanding to spiders, that spin webs from themselves; the thinking experience (which is his own) to the bees, that collect and separate at the same time. He says: “ Those who have hitherto treated of the sciences have been either empiricists or dog- matists. The former, like ants, only heap up, and use what they have collected; the latter, like spiders, spin webs out of themselves; the method of the bee is between these, it collects matter THE ANT, THE SPIDER, AND THE BEE, 11] from the gardens and the fields, but converts and digests it through its own faculty. Nor does the true labour of philosophy differ from that of the bee; for it relies neither solely nor principally on the powers of the mind, nor does it store up un- digested in the memory the matter derived from Natural History and mechanical experiments, but it stores such matter in the understanding, after first modifying and subduing it. Therefore, from a closer and purer alliance of these faculties (the experimental and the rational) than has yet been accomplished, we have much to hope.”* The matter collected by experience is wrought into science by methodic treatment; that is to say, by true induction, in relation to which it stands as an utensil to be employed, or as a wood to be cleared. f * “Qui tractaverunt scientias aut Empirici aut Dogmatici fuerunt. Empirici, formice more, congerunt tantum et utuntur ; Rationales, aranearum more, telas ex se conficiunt : apis vero ratio media est, que materiam ex floribus horti et agri elicit, sed tamen eam propria facultate vertit et digerit. Neque absimile philosophiz verum opificium est; quod nec mentis viribus tantum aut preecipue nititur, neque ex historia naturali et mechanicis experimentis prebitam materiam, in memoria in- tegram, sed in intellectu mutatam et subactam, reponit. Itaque ex harum facultatum (experimentalis scilicet et rationalis) arctiore et sanctiore foedere (quod adhuc factum non est) bene sperandum est.”—Vov. Org. I. 95. Compare also Cogitata et Visa. + Thus in the “ Parasceve” Bacon describes the “ Historia Naturalis” as “ vere: inductionis supellex sui silva.” 1b’. FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. Ill. InpvuctTion AND DEDUCTION IN THE BACONIAN SCIENCE. Thus the first problem is solved. It is shown how pure experience proceeds from doubt or the des- truction of idols, and how this experience results in science. It is shown what road leads from observation to law, from experiment to axiom. The sensuous perception with which experience sets out frees itself from z¢s idols (delusions of the senses) by rectifying experiments. ‘The inference of the law from the fact, with which experience ends, frees itself from zs idols (fallacious conclu- sions) by a careful consideration of negative in- stances and a comparison of them with the positive. This comparison is the second experiment. I, as it were, ask nature whether the law that is found is true, and will stand every test. “ An expe- Bees a riment,” says a modern writer, “is a question .) lod, a which nature gives the reply.” This propositio is so correct that we may also assert its converse. Every question put to nature is an experiment; and I question nature by directing myself to her instances, and compelling them to render an account of themselves. Nature is compared by Bacon to Proteus, who only answers when he is EXPERIMENT THE MEANS OF INVENTION. 113 compelled and bound.* The first experiment rectifies the perception, the second rectifies the inference. The question, then, that remains is this: how can knowledge, attained by the way of experience, become invention? For invention is the goal which is steadily kept in view by the Baconian philo- sophy. ‘The simple answer is: by the applica- tion of the discovered laws. If this application is possible, invention cannot fail. If I know the forces by which lightning is guided and attract- ed, I am certain of my lightning-conductor as soon as the required forces are at my disposal. This application of known natural forces is a new question to nature, practically put, —a new experiment, Therefore experiment is not only the means by which experience becomes science, but also the means by which science becomes in- j vention. Making experiments, I proceed from observation to axiom, from axiom to invention. “There is left for us,” says Bacon, “ pure expe- rience, which, if it offers itself, is called chance ; if it is sought, is called experiment. But this kind of experience is nothing but a broom without a band (as the saying is), a mere groping in the dark, as of men who, at night, try all means of * Compare “De Augm. Scient.” II. 2. Also the “ Wisdom of the Ancients,” 13. I 114 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. discovering the right road, when it would be much more expedient to wait for the dawn of day, or to kindle a light and then proceed. On the contrary, the true order of experience first kindles the light, then shows the way by means of this light; beginning with a regulated and digested, not a misplaced and erratic course of experiment, thence deducing axioms, and then, from the axioms thus established, making new ex- periments. Not even the Divine Word operated on the mass of things without order. Let men, therefore, cease to wonder, if the whole course of science be not run, when they have altogether wandered from the path; quitting and deserting experience entirely, or entangling themselves and roaming about in it, as in a labyrinth; when a true orderly method would lead them by a sure path through the woods of experience to the open daylight of axioms.” * * «*Restat experientia mera, que, si occurrat, casus; Si quesita sit, experimentum nominatur. Hoc autem experientie genus nihil aliud est, quam (quod aiunt) scope dissolute, et mera palpatio, quali homines noctu utuntur, omnia pertentando, si forte in rectam viam incidere detur ; quibus multo satius et consultius foret diem prestolari, aut lumen accendere, et dein- ceps viam inire. At contra, verus experientie ordo primo lumen accendit, deinde per lumen iter demonstrat, incipiendo ab experientia ordinata et digesta, et minime prepostera aut erratica, atque ex ea educendo axiomata, atque ex axiomatibus constitutis rursus experimenta nova ; quum nec verbum divyinum INDUCTION AND DEDUCTION. 115 The Baconian Induction proceeds from expe- riment to axiom; the Baconian deduction from axiom to experiment.* ‘The former is the me- thod of interpretation, the latter that of appli- cation. The former ends with the discovery of a law, the latter with an invention. Thus does Bacon’s philosophy, like his life, terminate with the triumph of experiment. in rerum massam absque ordine operatum sit. Itaque desinant homines mirari si spatium scientiarum non confectum sit, cum a via omnino aberraverint; relicta prorsus et deserta experientia, aut in ipsa (tanquam in labyrintho) se intricando et circumcur- sando ; cum rite institutus ordo per experientix sylvas ad aperta axiomatum tramite constanti ducat.” — Nov. Org. I. 82. (With respect to the curious expression, “ Scope dissolute,” which occurs in this passage, and which is rendered above, “a broom without a band,” Mr. Spedding remarks: “I do not remember any proverbial expression which answers to this in English ; but the allusion is to the want of combination and coherency in these experiments.”—J. O.) * Compare these words: “ Indicia de Interpretatione Natura complectuntur partes in genere duas ; primam de educendis aut excitandis axiomatibus ab experientia; secundam de deducen- dis aut derivandis experimentis novis ab axiomatibus.” — ov, Org. II. 10. (In the places marked by italics, Dr. Fischer respectively reads “ Judicia” and “ experimentis.” — J. O.) 12 116 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM, CHAT ON PREROGATIVE INSTANCES AS AIDS TO INDUCTION.—NATURAL ANALOGIES AS PREROGATIVE INSTANCES. Tue difficulties to which the method of induction is exposed from a scientific point of view are obvious; and Bacon was not the man to conceal from himself the difficulties of his subject, either through fear or negligence. Indeed, difficulties that terrify others are to him no more than in- citements that stimulate his enterprising and cir- cumspect mind. He seeks them out, and makes them conspicuous in order to remove them by as many expedients as he can discover. In such expedients, when he has found them, Bacon really triumphs. Here he is in his proper element ;— endowed, not with a systematic, but with an in- ventive intellect. To judge him as a system- maker (a character to which he does not aspire), is simply to misunderstand him; he is not to be in the least confuted by the proof that his method is fragmentary, and leads to no final result. Such a proof would be as easy as it would be value- less. Bacon himself would willingly bear the EXPEDIENTS AGAINST DIFFICULTIES. 117 reproach, and would convert it into a defence. “It is the very nature of my method,” he would say, “that it neither seeks nor desires a final result. If I have indicated the necessary goals, shown the right way, travelled part of this way myself, removed difficulties, and devised expedi- ents, I have done enough, and may leave the rest to future generations. They will go further than I; but it is to be hoped they will not arrive at an absolute conclusion. It is sufficient, to guide men into the path of progressive cultivation, to fur- nish them with means for the extension of their knowledge, and consequently of their dominion. On this path every point affords a triumph, and constitutes a goal in itself. As for the last goal, —the conclusion of all toil,—those alone can reach it who take no part in the great race of human faculties.” Thoroughly to understand such “eo minds as that of Bacon, we must look for them where their own method leaves them in the lurch; where they are forced to exert their own per- sonal faculties; where they are compelled to fill up the gaps in their theory by means of their genius, of their individual tact, of that something which I may call the generalship of philosophy. If Bacon’s historical importance is most con- spicuous when he formulises his problem, and propounds his method, his personal peculiarity, rs 118 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. his own especial talent is most visibly shown when, with expedients of his own invention, he defends himself against the difficulties by which his method is impeded. Here we can see who is master and who is disciple; for it commonly happens that a gap in the master’s method is also a gap in the head of the scholar, but none at all in the head of the master. Thus, even at the present day, the disciples of Bacon boast much of Bacon’s method when they oppose the contrary tendency, which is its complement. They do not know how much this tendency was akin to the mind of Bacon; how he grasped it involuntarily and instinctively when his method abandoned him. They do not know that he, the master, clearly pereeived those defects in his method which they, the disciples, would willingly ignore. When Bacon can proceed no further as an expe- rimental investigator of nature, he becomes, in spite of his method, a speculative natural philo- -sopher. We have designedly pointed out the affinity between Bacon and his intellectual anti- podes, that we may show how comprehensively he thought, and how he could complete himself from his own resources. ‘Thus, in the founda- tion of philosophy, he agreed with Descartes ; in his physical views, with Spinoza; and even in the auxiliary forces (Hiilfstruppen) of his DEFECTS OF THE BACONIAN METHOD. 119 philosophy a similarity to the speculative ideas of Leibnitz, Herder, and Schelling may be dis- covered, I. Tue Derects or tar BaconrAn MErTuHOp. What is the purpose of the inductive method in Bacon’s sense of the word? It would reduce natural science to axioms as indisputable as those of mathematics, and these axioms it would discover on the path of critical experience by an unre- mitting observation of negative instances. Now here arises a double difficulty : 1, The observation of negative instances by no means implies their exhaustion; and yet they must be exhausted if an axiom is to be established. Against the axiom it must no longer be possible to oppose a single negative instance; and this impossibility must be capable of demonstration.* That we cease to find negative instances is not enough; we must also be able to prove that there are really no more. Now this proof can never be furnished by experience, which cannot even assert, much less prove, that a contradictory instance is impossible; for nature is richer than experience. Bacon rightly desires that science * Vide p. 104, 14 120 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. should seek after axioms in that sense of thorough universality and necessity that prohibits any exception. But this very universality, in all its strictness, is never to be completely attained by the way of experience, but can only be approached, By the method of induction, the negative instances can never be drained to the lees. 2. But the very observation of negative in- stances, consisting as it does of a careful com- parison between positive and contradictory cases, is attended with difficulty. So long as these cases balance each other, very many of them must be collected, and an accurate comparison must be continued through a long series of them, before we can so much as attempt to deduce an axiom from the facts before us. iverything depends on the exclusion of contingencies; and to effect this purpose many cases, much time, and much labour, are required. An inference drawn from a few cases has manifestly more to fear from negative instances than one that has been drawn from many. In the number, therefore, of cases compared, lies the only possible guarantee against the existence of negative instances. PREROGATIVE INSTANCES, 121 II. Tue PREROGATIVE INSTANCES. The difficulties are manifest. Means are to be sought for removing, or at least lightening them. Such means are the auzilia mentis, enumerated by Bacon, who, moreover, expatiates fully on one of them in the second book of his “ Novum Organum.” * This one expedient is the chief of them all; its use is to support the method by completing it on the one hand, and facilitating it on the other. The method consists in the separation of contingent from necessary conditions, and its difficulty lies in the breadth of the required material,— in the tediousness, minuteness, and insecurity of the comparison. By facilitating the work of separation, we likewise shorten it, rendering the contingent conditions more easily discernible, the essential more capable of super- vision. This can only be effected by reducing the many cases to a few, so that a few will serve me in the place of many. But by what right can I do this? So long as one case is as worthy * Compare Nov. Org. II. 21—52. The second vol. of the “Novum Organum” is unfinished, as well as the “ Instauratio Magna,” of which the whole “ Novum Organum” was to have formed the second part. 122 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. of attention as another, so long as in this respect opposite cases are equally balanced, we must obviously have many of them before we can make any efficient comparison at all. But if there are certain cases, one of which is equal in value to a series of others, we shall then rightly consider one of the former, instead of many of the latter, and thus the more speedily obtain our result. Such cases are more worthy of our observation than the rest, and have, by their very nature, a sort of prerogative. Hence they are called “ prerogative instances” by Bacon. » Without doubt there are cases in which a given natural phenomenon is exhibited more purely and free from mixture than in others; in which the contingent circumstances, being fewer, may be more rapidly excluded, and therefore the essential conditions more easily and clearly ascer- tained. A prerogative instance facilitates the work of separation, inasmuch as it shows me, almost at a single glance, the true difference (vera differentia), the operative nature, the law of the phenomenon. What I should otherwise be forced to seek with great toil, and by a tedious comparison from a multitude of instances, I here find at once presented in a single phenomenon. Thus, for example, if the question is of specific eravity, the mere fact that quicksilver is so much THEORY OF COLOUR. 123 heavier than gold is sufficient to show that the specific gravity of a body is regulated by its mass, not by the cohesion of its parts. This one observation will save me many others.* Or if the question is respecting a phenomenon that is to be found in all bodies, I shall find the purest specimen in such bodies that have little or nothing in common with others. Such “ solitary in- stances,” as Bacon calls them, save us the trouble y of future comparison. Thus, for example, the phenomenon of colour is discovered most readily, and with the least heterogeneous admixture, in prisms, crystals, and dewdrops; for these have little or nothing in common with other coloured bodies, such as flowers, stones, metals, varieties of wood, &c. They are, in this respect, single instances (instantie solitarie); and from observing them we easily arrive at the result, that “colour is nothing but a modification of the image of the incident and absorbed light; in the former case, by the different degrees of incidence; in the latter, by the textures and various forms of bodies.” f * Such prerogative instances are called by Bacon: Ostensive, Liberatx, Preedominantes, and Elucescentis, Nov. Org. IT. 24. T “Facile colligitur quod color nil aliud sit quam modificatio imaginis lucis immisse et recepte ; in priore genere per gradus diversos incidentix, in posteriore per texturas et varios schema- tismos corporis.” 124 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. Géothe, in his “ Materials towards the History of the Theory of Colours,” has made mention of Bacon ; but, strangely enough, he has not cited this remarkable passage. Evidently he was not aware of it; for, if he had been, he would cer- tainly have referred to it, inasmuch as it confirms his own view. In fact, it contains the principle of Gdéthe’s theory before Newton. Gidthe is altogether ignorant of the Baconian theory of Prerogative Instances, otherwise he would not have said that to Bacon, in the broad region of phenomena, all things were alike. Indeed, he treats the general method of Bacon with too much contempt, ranking it no higher than ordinary ex- perience, and accusing it of leading mankind to a boundless empiricism, “ whereby they acquired such a horror of all method, that they regarded chaotic disorder as the only soil in which science could really thrive.” This reproach applies to most of those who, at the present day, profess to be followers of Bacon, but not to Bacon himself, whose intellect was not only methodical, but even speculative. His explanation of the phenomenon of colour, which is merely given by way of ex- ample, while he is treating of another subject, expresses the same fundamental thought that Gothe sought to establish,—as he believed, for the first time,—against Newton. Gothe says of NATURAL ANALOGIES. 125 Newton’s Theory of Colours: —“ By his desire to keep light alone in view, Newton seems to set out from a simple principle, but he imposes con- ditions upon it, as we do; while, however, he denies their integrating part in producing the result.” These conditions are bodies transparent and opaque, and the share that they take in the pro- duction of colour is clearly and definitely declared by Bacon in the passage cited above. * Ill. Naturat ANALOGIEs. Prerogative Instances, of which Bacon enu- » merates twenty-seven, are phenomena that pre- eminently rivet, and, moreover, merit our atten- tion. “They are pregnant instances from which much may be inferred by an accelerated induc- tion, by a rapid separation of the contingent from . the necessary.| But, according to Bacon, all induction, all methodical experience is directed towards real natural philosophy, which, like every earnest science, necessarily strives after perfection, and, from a knowledge of the individual, seeks a knowledge of the universal. To this truly scien- tific impulse Bacon was by no means foreign. Like every other great thinker, he possessed it; * Vide Appendix B. a nee 126 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. the knowledge of the whole was ever before his eyes, as the last point to which natural science should tend; only, according to his view, it should be attained by the labour of bees, not by that of spiders. Induction proceeds from observation to axiom, from fact to law ; when it has explained a few facts, it is naturally impelled to explain more, to extend the compass of its laws, and to progress continually in the generalisation of its axioms. The most universal axiom is that of entire nature; the highest law is that which explains a// phenomena. As every law expresses the unity of certain phe- nomena, so does this highest law express the unity of nature as a whole; the unitas nature. This is the goal which Bacon proposes to science ; to this his method is expressly directed. He did not lay down the unity of nature as a principle, but would learn it from nature herself, would infer it from her phenomena. Like Spinoza, he sees in things a natura naturata, at the basis of which, as an operative power, lies the natura naturans, which, in his eyes, .is also a common source of all things, —a unitas nature. However, while Spinoza, from the xatura naturans would deduce the naturata, Bacon, on the other hand, would fem the naturata induce the naturans. He therefore seeks phenomena in nature, that point to the unity of the whole, open a view into NATURAL ANALOGIES. 127 the unity of entire nature, and thus assist the inferences of induction. If there are certain phenomena which, more than others, lead us to surmise the unity of the whole, they rivet our at- tention, when directed to the whole, as so many prerogative instances. Of what kind these preg- nant instances must be, is obvious enough. They are the prominent resemblances in the various formations of nature, the significant analogies that announce to us a unanimity in the operative forces. Here Bacon regards induction in the light of analogy, that is, he leads the investiga-_ tions of physical science to the affinity of things, by directing them to the unity of the whole.* He shows as it were nature’s family likenesses, and we have now to find the pedigree of things, together with its roots. In the exhibition of analogies, Bacon displays a characteristic peculiarity of his mind. ‘To re- gard induction in the light of analogy, the things analogous must be discovered and correctly ob- served. Now the discovery is made not by the method, but by the eye of the investigator; the method follows the discovery, when the latter is ii a “eleteepet * Compare Nor. Org. I. 27: “Inter Prerogativas Instan- tiarum ponemus sexto loco Instantias conformes, sive propor- tionatas ; quas etiam parallelas, sive similitudines physicas, appel- lare consuevimus.” 128 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. already made. Moreover, it is not by mere sen- suous perception, though aided by artificial in- struments, that analogies are detected, but by the further penetration of the mind. “The important _ analogies are those internal, secret resemblances, . that are not to be found on the surface of things, —not to be apprehended at a glance by the senses. A speculative spirit, a genius for investigation, must seek them out; the tact that accompanies genius must light upon them. Both these may be methodically cultivated, but neither can be given. Every true analogy is a correct combination made by a judicious intellect. Dexterous as Bacon is in supporting his method by means of striking combinations, he still cautiously restrains the readily combining intellect by the aid of his methodical spirit. I will not assert that Bacon himself never transcended these bounds, that all his analogies were as felicitous as they are bold and ingenious; but with respect to the scope and scientific value of analogy, he was _ perfectly clear. He sought an equilibrium between his genius and his method; by which, alternately, his mind was ever influenced. yen before he adduces his analogies —(as mere examples, which he scatters about heedlessly as he goes along, but which would afford an ample sus- tenance to many a natural philosopher of modern USE OF ANALOGIES. 129 times), he sets judicious limits to their importance, and the use that is to be made of them. To him they appear rather as suggestive than as sources of exact knowledge, and serve more to direct the , contemplative understanding to the whole than — to instruct it in details. The analogies are, as it were, the first chords that we hear of the harmony of the universe. -* They are, as it were,” says Bacon, “the first and truest steps towards the union of nature. They do not at once establish an axiom, but only indicate and observe a certain conformity of bodies to each other. But although they do not conduce much to the discovery of general laws (or forms), they are, nevertheless, of great service in disclosing the fabrication of parts of the universe, and practise a sort of anatomy upon its members. Thence they sometimes lead us, as if by hand, to sublime and noble axioms, espe- cially those that relate to the configuration of the world rather than to simple natures and forms. * “Sunt tanquam primi et infimi gradus ad unionem Nature. Neque constituunt aliquod axioma statim ab initio, sed indicant et observant tantum quendam consensum corporum, Attamen licet non multum promoveant ad inveniendas formas, nihilo- minus magna cum utilitate revelant partium universi fabricam, et in membris ejus exercent veluti anatomiam quandam ; atque proinde veluti manu-ducunt interdum ad axiomata sublimia et nobilia, presertim illa que ad mundi configurationem perti- nent, potius quam ad naturas et formas simplices.” — JVov. Org. IL. 27. < Wx K 9* | 130 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. And even while Bacon is occupied in setting forth his analogies, which rush through the world with the boldest combinations, he interrupts him- self, remarks anew the use of analogy to science, and also the danger to which this sort of combina- tion is exposed. This is quite right. It is only with the aid of analogy that induction can bring real unity into natural science, and discover that spiritual connection of things that can never be found through a mere description of parts, and is at last lost sight of altogether. ‘It is especially to be recommended, and more frequently to be suggested, that the diligence of man in the in- vestigation and compilation of natural history be henceforward entirely changed and converted to the contrary of that which has been hitherto in use. Hitherto the industry of man has been great and curious in noting the variety of things, and in ex- plaining the accurate differences of animals, vege- tables, and minerals, many of which are rather the sport of nature than of any real utility to science. Things of this sort are amusing, and sometimes not without practical use, but they con- tribute little or nothing towards the investigation of nature. Our labour, therefore, must be re- versed, and directed to the inquiry and notation of the resemblances and analogies of things, both in the whole and in part. For these analogies UNITY MORE IMPORTANT THAN VARIETY. 131 unite nature, and lay the foundation of science.” * “It seems of no great utility to recount or know the marvellous varieties of flowers, whether of iris or tulip, of shells, dogs, or hawks. For things of this sort are nothing but the sports and wanton- ness of nature, and nearly approach the nature of individuals. By means of these we have a minute knowledge of things, but scanty and often unpro- fitable information with respect to science. Yet these are the things of which common natural history makes a boast.” Nevertheless, analogies must be cautiously and critically sought; for if, * “Tilud omnino precipiendum est et sepius monendum, ut diligentia hominum in inquisitione et congerie Naturalis Histo- riz deinceps mutetur plane, et vertatur in contrarium ejus quod nunc in usu est. Magna enim hucusque atque adeo curiosa fuit hominum industria in notanda rerum varietate atque expli- candis accuratis animalium, herbarum, et fossilium differentiis; quarum plereeque magis sunt lusus nature quam serie alicujus utilitatis versus scientias. Faciunt certe hujusmodi res ad delectationem, atque etiam quandoque ad praxin; verum ad introspiciendam naturam parum aut nihil. Itaque convertenda plane est opera ad inquirendas et notandas rerum similitudines et analoga, tam in integralibus quam partibus. Illx enim sunt que naturam uniunt, et constituere scientias incipiunt.” — Nov. Org. IL. 27. T “Non multum ad rem faciunt memorare aut nosse florum, iris aut tulips, aut etiam concharum aut canum aut accipitrum eximias varietates. Hee enim hujusmodi nil aliud sunt quam nature lusus quidem et lascivia ; et prope ad naturam indivi- duorum accedunt. Itaque habent cognitionem in rebus ipsis exquisitam; informationem vero ad scientias tenuem et fere supervacuam. Atque hee sunt tamen illa in quibus naturalis K 2 132 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. on the one hand, the endless varieties of things are often a mere sport of nature, so may the analogies, discovered by our own combinations, easily prove. to be a mere sport of the under- standing or the imagination. We make analogies that are not in nature; find analogies that in truth are none; fix our attention on casual, non- essential points of resemblance, and thus infer much from that which says nothing. Sports of this sort, to which a speculative and heedless imagination or a dreamy intellect willingly aban- dons itself, have peopled the region of natural science with a multitude of idols. If analogies are to be fruitful in results, they must embrace ¢ essential resemblances ; they must be, as it were, learned by listening at the secret workshop of nature. Hence Bacon proceeds to insist : * That in all these (analogies) a severe and rigorous caution be observed, that we only accept, as simi- lar and proportionate instances, those that denote natural resemblances, — that is to say, real, sub- stantial, and immersed_in_nature; not merely casual and superficial, much less superstitious or exceptional, like those always brought forward by historia vulgaris se jactat.”— Descript. Globi Intellectualis, cap. iii. [This citation is added to the note in the original, but it accords so well with the language of the text, that I have ventured to place it there. —J. O.] BOLDNESS OF BACON’S ANALOGIES. 133 the writers on natural magic (men of the least account, and scarcely worthy of mention in serious matters, such as those of which we now treat), who with much vanity and folly describe, and some- times invent, idle resemblances and sympathies.”* The analogies themselves, that Bacon cites as examples, are of the boldest kind, seeing far and anticipating much, — attractive points of view, affording a rich and fertile prospect. With a few strokes he sketches the great pedigree of things, and shows by themost comprehensive combinations how everything in the world belongs to one family. Never, perhaps, was such a promising view into the connection of the universe afforded in the form of concise aphorism and cursory example. Bacon begins by comparing the mirror with the eye; the ear with the echo. The mirror and the eye reflect rays of light; the ear and the echo reflect the undulations of sound. Bacon concludes that there is a general analogy between the organs * “Verum in his omnino est adhibenda cautio gravis et severa, ut accipiantur pro instantiis conformibus et propor- tionatis, ille que denotant similitudines physicas; id est, rea- les et substantiales et immersas in natura, non fortuitas et ad speciem; multo minus superstitiosas aut curiosas, quales naturalis magi scriptores (homines levissimi, et in rebus tam seriis quales nune agimus vix nominandi) ubique ostentant; magna cum vanitate et desipientia, inanes similitudines et sym- pathias rerum describentes atque etiam quandoque affingentes.” — Lib. II. 27, K 3 | } 134 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. of sense and reflecting bodies; between organic and inorganic nature. The idea of an analogy pervading all natural phenomena is clearly before his mind. All the relations and moods of inani- mate nature are perceptible, and when they are not perceived by us, this is owing to the nature of our own bodies, to which so many senses are wanting ; however, there are more (or at least as many) movements in inanimate than senses in animated bodies. Thus, for example, as many kinds of painful sensation as are possible to the human frame, so many kinds of motion, such as squeezing, pricking, contraction, extension, &c., are there in inanimate bodies; only these, through the want of vitality, do not feel them.” * The comparison between organic and inorga- nic nature in general is carried by Bacon into analogies between details. He remarks similar formations between plants and stones, and by way of example compares gum with certain gems. These, according to him, are exudations and filterings (percolationes) of juices, the sap of trees exuding in the shape of gum; the moisture of rocks, after the same fashion, as a transparent gem. Hence the brightness and clearness of the vegetable and mineral formations, both of which * These analogies are all to be found in ov. Org. lib. \ IL 27. INSTANCES OF ANALOGY. 135 are, as it were, filtered juices. Thus, among animals, the wings of birds are more beautiful and more vividly coloured than the hair of beasts, because the juices are not so delicately filtered through the thick skin as through the quills. In the formation of plants Bacon remarks a similar structure in the different parts, and in the spirit of modern morphology (which arose so long after him) calls attention to the fact, that in vegetable growth the constituent parts, both above and below, spread out towards the circumference. In their position, at opposite extremities of the plant, Bacon finds the only distinction between the branches and the roots. The roots are branches working their way downwards into the earth; the branches are roots striving upwards towards the air and sun. In the animal kingdom Bacon compares the fins of fishes with the feet of qua- drupeds, and the feet and wings of birds; and the formation of teeth with that of beaks. The structure of the plant he compares with that of man, saying that the latter is, as it were, a plant inverted (planta inversa). The brain in man, whence the nerves take their origin, to spread in countless ramifications through the entire frame, corresponds to the root in plants. To no one were the analogies between man and plant more attractive than to Herder, who was never K4 136 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. weary of spinning out and repeating this simile with every possible variation. It was a fault in him that he used this planta inversa as a characteristic of man, which he could interpret as a symbol of universal history. Herder’s intel- lect was made for analogies. Every analogy was a theme, on which he could compose a fantasia, and indeed what he called his “ Ideas” were mere analogies after all. From such points of view he derived his theories of the history of mankind. His combinations were generally sug- gestive, seldom accurate, and he might serve as an eminent example to illustrate the genius of analogy, with all its aberrations and its blunders. To this point especially did Kant direct his shafts in his critique of Herder’s “ Ideas,” show- ing how frequently his analogies were uncertain, and the conclusions drawn from them false. Bacon treats the analogies which he introduces into natural science with great tact; he does not play with them, but contents himself with noting the point of resemblance, and explaining it in a few words; after which he hastens on to new comparisons. From definite imstances he infers universal analogies, which ultimately com- prehend all nature, and these axioms he confirms anew by fresh definite instances, —by special com- ‘parisons between minerals and plants, plants and u GEOGRAPHICAL ANALOGY. 137 animals, &c. Beginning with individual instances, he at last directs his glance to the relations of the whole world, and already anticipating the speculative geography of our own time, observes the analogies in the formation of the quarters of the globe. Thus he is struck by the re- semblance between Africa and South America, both of which extend over the Southern Hemi- sphere, while there is a further analogy between the isthmus and promontory of both. “ This is no mere accident ” (non temere accidit), he signifi- cantly adds. He embraces both the Old and the New World in one comparative view, and remarks that these two huge masses of land become broad as they approach the north, narrow and pointed as they approach the south. There is something great and striking in the very fact of these re- marks; in the fact that here also Bacon has discovered an analogy, which, without difficulty, can be followed into its details. In a few short hints, given in a cursory manner, he has recognised a most interesting point in geogra- phical science, namely, the importance to be attached to the variations of the line of coast. By way of conclusion, Bacon essays his compa- rative glance on arts and sciences, and here also seeks for analogies. He takes for his examples rhetoric and music, mathematics and logic; find- 138 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. ing in the former similar tropes, in the latter similar forms of reasoning. To the rhetorical figure called preter expectationem, the musical declinatio cadentie perfectly corresponds. In ma- thematics there is the axiom that “things equal to the same are equal to one another.” To this there is a complete analogy in the logical form of syllogism, which connects two terms by means of a third. We do not pronounce a judgment on the scientific value and scope of all these analogies which Bacon uses as examples. To us they are important for the assistance they afford us, both by their subject-matter, and by the manner of their introduction, in arriving at a right know- ledge of Bacon himself. They show a mind of the most comprehensive vision, with a corre- sponding acuteness in observing combinations. | Bacon does not use an analogy as an object, but as an instrument in aid of his method. Of this ~ Gnstrument he makes lavish use, according to the dictates of his own inclination and abundant power; he extends his grasp beyond the limits of his method, and, in spite of all his caution, there is imminent danger that he will not only abandon this method, but act in direct opposition to it; for, in truth, every analogy is an anticipatio mentis. The very design of Bacon’s analogies shows that ANALOGY SUPPLEMENTARY TO INDUCTION. 139 | he sought more than can be afforded by experience. He sought by this road what he could not discover by that of induction alone, namely, the unity of nature as manifested in the affinity of all things, or the harmony of the universe. Here we find Bacon in alliance with Leibnitz and his fol- lowers, as we found him before with Spinoza and Descartes. It will be but fair if we take that comparative view of Bacon himself which he took of all nature, pointing out his own mental affinities, his own analogies, and aiding our ob- servation by his “parallel instances,” which do nothing to diminish his originality, but throw a light on his comprehensive mind. What was fundamental tendency in Leibnitz was supple- mentary in Bacon, so that the axiom of the for- mer was the auxiliary expedient of the latter. Leibnitz as much needed induction as Bacon needed analogy. The mind of Bacon extends further than his method; but in this very circumstance lies his epoch-making power, and it imposes upon us the necessity of comprehending his antagonism to antiquity and the philosophy derived from it. Thus we shall place ourselves in Bacon’s own mental sphere and picture to ourselves that an- tagonism, just as Bacon himself conceived it. 140 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. CHAP. VI. THE PHILOSOPHY OF BACON IN ITS RELATION TO THE PHILOSOPHY PRECEDING IT. THE result of the Baconian philosophy, and the logical order of its ideas, may be thus stated in its principal features : — 1. Science should serve man by being use- ful to him. Its use consists in inventions; the object of which is the dominion of the human race. 2. Science can only become inventive through an exact knowledge of things, and this is only to be obtained by an interpretation of nature. 3. A correct interpretation of nature is only possible through pure and methodical experience. Experience is pure when it does not judge ac- cording to “idols” and human analogies, when it does not anthropomorphise things, when it is, mere experimentalising perception. LExpe- rience is methodical as true induction. Induction is true when, by an accurate and critical com- parison, it infers laws from a number of particular instances. Comparison is critical when it opposes OPPOSITION TO ANTIQUITY. 141 negative to positive instances. Moreover, the process of inductive reasoning is accelerated by the investigation of prerogative instances. Ex- perience, thus disciplined, avoids from first to last all uncertain and premature hypotheses. Thus Bacon sets up his principle and himself in opposition to the past. He sees that his own principles comprise all the conditions requisite for a thorough renovation of science, such as no one before him had the courage or the vigour to effect ; he feels that he is himself the bearer of the renovating spirit, — the scientific reformer. ** No one,” he says, “ has as yet been found en- dowed with sufficient firmness and vigour to re- solve upon and undertake the thorough abolition of common theories and notions, and the fresh application of the intellect, thus cleared and rendered impartial, to the study of particulars, Hence human reason, such as we have it now, is a mere farrago and crude mass made up of much credulity, much accident, and, withal, of those puerile notions which are imbibed early in life, But if some one of mature age, sound senses, and a disabused mind, should apply himself anew to experience and the study of particulars, we might have better hope of him.”* « Some hope might, * “Nemo adhuc tanta mentis constantia et rigore inventus est, ut dicaverit et sibi imposuerit theorias et notiones communes 142 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. we think, be afforded by my own example; and we do not say this for the sake of boasting, but because it may be useful. If any feel a want of confidence, let them look at me,—a man who, among his contemporaries, has been most en- gaged in public affairs, who is of somewhat infirm health (which of itself occasions great loss of time), and who, in this matter, is assuredly the first explorer, neither following in the steps of another, nor communicating his own thoughts to a single individual; but who, nevertheless, having once firmly entered upon the right way, and submitted his mind to things, has (I think) made some advance.” * If we now compare Bacon’s philosophy with penitus abolere, et intellectum abrasum et equum ad particularia de integro applicare. Itaque ratio illa humana quam habemus, ex multa fide et multo etiam casu, nec non ex puerilibus quas primo hausimus notionibus, farrago quedam est et congeries. Quod si quis state matura et sensibus integris et mente repur- gata se ad experientiam et ad particularia de integro applicet, de eo melius sperandum est.” — Nov. Org. I. 97. * «Etiam nonnihil hominibus spei fieri posse putamus ab exemplo nostro proprio; neque jactantize causa hoc dicimus sed quod utile dictu sit. Si qui diffidant, me videant, hominem inter homines eetatis mez civilibus negotiis occupatissimum, nec firma admodum valetudine (quod magnum habet temporis dispen- dium), atque in hac re plane protopirum, et vestigia nullius secutum, neque hec ipsa cum ullo mortalium communicantem, et tamen veram viam constanter ingressum et ingenium rebus submittentem, heec ipsa aliquatenus (ut existimamus) provexisse.” — Nov. Org. I. 113. BACON AND KANT. 143 that which preceded it, we find, in all those points that bear upon the reformation of science, a de- cided antagonism. Bacon gives science another purpose, another foundation, another tendency. I. Tue Practicat Enp. DOGMATISM AND SCEPTICISM. Bacon immediately directs science to the use of mankind, and to invention as the agent for promoting it; he would make science practical and generally useful, and from this point of view opposes the scientific character previously recognised, which was theoretic and only acces- sible to the few. From an affair of the schools, which it had hitherto been, Bacon would make of science an affair of life, not merely because it suited his inclination so to do, but as a necessary consequence of his principles. Bacon’s plan of renovation stands in an opposition to the an- tique, similar to that of the Kantian philosophy, Kant would make philosophy critical; Bacon would make it practical. Preceding systems appear uncritical to Kant, unpractical to Bacon. In the summary judgment which both, from opposite points of view, pronounce upon their predecessors, both are alike incapable of doing 144 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. justice in any particular to the philosophical culture of the past. They both agree that all preceding philosophy has been mere fruitless spe- culation, that the systems of the past fall into the opposite extremes of dogmatism and scepticism, and thus reciprocally annul each other’s results. To Kant the representatives of dogmatic and sceptical philosophy were Wolf and Hume; to Bacon they were the dogmatic Aristotelians and the academical sceptics, of whom he said that the former came to false and rash conclusions, the latter to none at all.* To embrace both these epochs of modern philosophy in one common expression, we may assert that Bacon and Kant, convinced of the fruitlessness of all preceding speculation, both desired to render philosophy fruitful, and therefore practical. Bacon directed it to a practical knowledge of nature, Kant to a practical knowledge of self. The ripest fruit of the Baconian philosophy is invention, so far as it conduces to the dominion of man; that of the Kantian is morality as based upon human free- dom and autonomy. Bacon is never weary of reproaching the past with unfruitfulness, as a necessary consequence of theoretical philosophy. People fancy that they know a great deal, through this traditional system; * Compare Nov. Org. 1. 67. STERILITY OF ANCIENT SCIENCE. 145 nevertheless they make no advance, but remain stationary and inactive. The belief in their wealth is the cause of their poverty.* “ That philosophy, which we have chiefly derived from the Greeks, appears to be, as it were, the childhood of science, being fertile in controversy, barren of effect. Moreover, if sciences of this sort had not been a dead letter, it seems highly improbable that they would have remained, as they have, almost im- movable on their ancient footing without acquiring growth worthy of the human race; and this to such an extent that frequently not only does an assertion remain an assertion, but even a question remains a question, and instead of being solved by discus-. sion is fixed and maintained, so that the whole tradition and succession of instruction exhibits as on a stage the characters of master and scholar, but not that of the inventor, or of him who has added anything excellent to inventions. In mechanical arts we find that the contrary is the case. These, as if they partook of some vivifying air, are daily increased and brought to perfection. On the contrary, philosophy and the intellectual sciences, like statues, are adored and celebrated like sta- tues, but are not moved from the spot whereon they stand.” f * Opinio copisz =Causa inopise. — Cogit. Visa. t “Et de utilitate aperte dicendum est, sapientiam istam L 146 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. Tl. Tue PuysicaAL FOUNDATION. Bacon, having decided that invention is the end of science, takes physics as its foundation. Thus he is in direct opposition to the philosophies of every preceding age; to scholasticism, which, at bottom, was nothing but theology, to the Roman philosophy, which was chiefly occupied with ethics, and to the Graco-classic, which based physics upon metaphysics. Bacon first shows that philosophy has hitherto been unfruit- ful; then he investigates the causes of this sci- entific poverty. The first of these causes he finds in the fact that of the whole period recorded in the history of mankind an extremely small portion quam a Grecis potissimum hausimus pueritiam quandam scientis videri. . . - Controversiarum enim ferax, operum effocta est. . - . Praterea, si hujusmodi scientiz plane res mortuz non essent, id minime videtur eventurum fuisse quod per multa jam secula usu venit, ut ille suis immote fere hereant vestigiis, nec incrementa genere humano digna sumant: eo usque, ut sepenumero non solum assertio maneat assertio sed etiam quzstio maneat questio, et per disputationes non solvatur sed figatur et alatur, omnisque traditio et successio discipli- narum representet et exhibeat personas magistri et auditoris, non inventoris et ejus qui inventis aliquid eximium adjiciat. In artibus autem mechanicis contrarium evenire videmus ; que, ac si aure cujusdam vitalis forent participes, quotidie crescunt et perficiuntur. . . . Philosophia contra et scientie intellec- tuales, statuarum more, adorantur et celebrantur, sed non pro- moventur.” — Pref. Inst. Magna, THE THREE EPOCHS OF LEARNING. 147 has been devoted to science, and the second in the fact that the smallest portion eyen of scientific labour has been bestowed upon the natural sciences. “ Of the five and twenty cen- turies, which nearly comprise all the memory and learning of man, scarcely six can be selected and set apart as fertile in science and favourable to its advancement. For deserts and wildernesses are no less in times than in countries, and we can rightly enumerate no more than three revolutions and epochs of learning, namely, first the Greek ; secondly, the Roman; and lastly, our own (that is to say, the learning of the Western nations of Europe); and to each of these scarcely two cen- turies can be justly assigned. Even in those ages, in which men’s wit and literature flourished greatly, or even moderately, the smallest part of human labour was bestowed upon Natural Phi- losophy, which ought nevertheless to be regarded as the great mother of all the sciences. For all the arts and sciences torn from this root may perhaps be polished and fitted for use, but they will scarcely grow. It is well known that after the Christian religion had been adopted and had reached maturity, by far the greater number of excellent wits devoted themselves to theology ; that to this science the highest rewards were offered, and all means of assistance were abun- L 2 148 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. dantly supplied; and that thus. the study of theology almost entirely occupied that third period which has been given as that of the Western Europeans; the rather because about the same time when literature began to flourish, religious contro- versies also began to bud forth. In the preceding age, during that second or Roman period, the me- ditation and labour of philosophers were chiefly occupied and consumed by moral philosophy, which held the place of theology among the heathens. Moreover, in those times the greatest minds applied themselves as much as possible to civil affairs, on account of the magnitude of the Roman Empire, which required the labour of many men. But that age, during which Natural Philosophy appeared to flourish chiefly among the Greeks, was exceedingly short, since, in the more ancient times, the seven wise men, as they were called, all (with the exception of Thales), devoted themselves to Moral Philosophy and Politics; and in the times succeeding, after So- crates had brought down philosophy from heaven to earth, moral philosophy became still more prevalent, and diverted the minds of men from natural science. In the meanwhile let no one expect great progress in the sciences (especially their operative part) unless Natural Philosophy be applied to particular sciences, and particular — THE THREE EPOCHS OF LEARNING. 149 sciences again referred to Natural Philosophy. Hence it arises that astronomy, optics, music, many mechanical arts, medicine itself (and what seems more wonderful) moral and political phi- losophy, have no depth, but only glide over the surface and variety of things; because these sciences, having been once partitioned out and established, are no longer nourished by Natural Philosophy. Thus, there is little cause for wonder that the sciences do not grow, when they are separated from their roots.” * * “Ex viginti quinque annorum centuriis, in quibus memoria et doctrina hominum fere versatur, vix sex centuriz seponi et excerpi possunt, que scientiarum feraces earumve proventui utiles fuerunt. Sunt enim non minus temporum quam regionum eremi et vastitates. Tres enim tantum doctrinarum revolutiones et periodi recte numerari possunt: una, apud Grecos ; altera, apud Romanos; ultima, apud nos, occidentales scilicet Europese nationes: quibus singulis vix due centuries annorum merito attribui possunt. . . . Per illas ipsas «tates quibus hominum ingenia et liter maxime vel etiam mediocriter floruerint, Naturalis Philosophia minimam partem humane opere sortita sit. Atque hee ipsa nihilominus pro magna scientiarum matre haberi debet. Omnes enim artes et scientise ab hac stirpe revulse, poliuntur fortasse et in usum effinguntur, sed nil admodum crescunt. At manifestum est, postquam Christiana fides recepta fuisset et adolevisset, longe maximam ingeniorum prestantis- simorum partem ad Theologiam se contulisse ; atque huic rei et amplissima premia proposita, et omnis generis adjumenta co- piosissime subministrata fuisse: atque hoc Thelogiz studium pracipue occupasse tertiam illam partem sive periodum temporis apud nos Europsos occidentales ; eo magis, quod sub idem fere tempus et litere florere et controversix circa religionem pul- L 3 150 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. Ill. THe ANTIFORMAL TENDENCY. That he may arrive at a proper explanation of nature, Bacon rejects all idols, including final causes, generic notions and forms, as human analogies that do not belong to the things them- selves. To final he opposes efficient causes ; to generic notions, individual things; to abstract julare coeperint. At evo superiori, durante periodo illa secunda apud Romanos, potissime philosophorum meditationes et indus- trie in Morali Philosophia (que Ethnicis vice Theologie erat) occupate et consumpte fuerunt: etiam summa ingenia illis temporibus ut plurimum ad res civiles se applicuerunt, propter magnitudinem imperii Romani, quod plurimorum hominum opera indigebat. At illa estas, qua Naturalis Philosophia apud Gracos maxime florere visa est, particula fuit temporis minime diuturna; cum et antiquioribus temporibus septem illi qui sapientes nominabantur, omnes (preter Thaletem) ad Moralem Philosophiam et civilia se applicuerint ; et posterio- ribus temporibus postquam Socrates philosophiam de ccelo in terras deduxisset, adhuc magis invaluerit Moralis Philosophia, et ingenia hominum a Naturali averterit. . . . Interimnemo expectet magnum progressum in scientiis (preesertim in parte earum operativa), nisi Philosophia Naturalis ad scientias parti- culares producta fuerit, et scientiz particulares rursus ad Natu- ralem Philosophiam reducte. Hine enim fit, ut astronomia, optica, musica, plurime artes mechanice, atque ipsa medicina, atque (quod quis magis miretur) philosophia moralis et civilis, et scientiz logice, nil fere habeant altitudinis in profundo ; sed per superficiem et varietatem rerum tantum labantur: quia postquam particulares ists scientiz dispertite ef constitute fuerint, a Philosophia Naturali non amplius alantur. . . . Itaque minime mirum est si scientiz non crescant, cum a radi- cibus suis sint separate.” — ov. Org. I. 78, 79, 80. POINTS OF OPPOSITION TO ANTIQUITY. 151 | forms, material qualities; and thus he denies I everything that would render an interpretation of ~ox--anatural, teleological, idealistic, or, in a word, ; { 7 | abstract. We may say, to combine these several oppositions in one single expression, that he em- ployed his whole weight to counterbalance that formal philosophy that had, down to his own time, so vastly preponderated, whether we consider the \ extent or the duration of its reign... Under.this- formal philosophy, which he regards as his an- tagonist, Bacon comprises Aristotelian Scholas- ticism, Platonic Aristotelism, Pythagorean Pla- tonism. In all these systems, that doctrine of final causes, that is regarded by Bacon as an *¢Tdolon Tribus,” predominates as the leading idea. The creations of formal philosophy are so many historical developments of this one fallacy. They are the idols that in the field of philosophy take possession of the human mind; that is to say, they are, in the eyes of Bacon, “ Idola Theatri.” * Such, accurately expressed, are the points of opposition that give an historical character to the Baconian philosophy. To theoretic it opposes practical philosophy as an instrument of useful cultivation; to metaphysics and theology, which have hitherto constituted the basis of science, it * The consideration of the “ Idola Theatri” occupies Apho- risms 61—68 of Nov. Org. lib. I. L4 152 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. opposes physics; to formal it opposes material philosophy ; to common experience it opposes scientific experience. 1. BACON’S ANTAGONISM TO ARISTOTLE. All these points of opposition were, as Bacon thought, concentrated in Aristotle, who, to his time, had held a dictatorship in the region of philosophy. Aristotle had ecanonised theory as the highest aspiration of the mind; rendering us similar to the gods. He had systematically ela- borated metaphysics, and upon this foundation had based his interpretation of nature. He was the real scientific representative of formal philo- sophy, and the creator of its logic; he regarded physics from the teleological point of view, after establishing that point of view metaphysically ; he brought the whole formal philosophy of the Greeks into a system, by which the middle ages were governed. Lastly, in Bacon’s eyes, that un- methodical and uncritical kind of experience that had hitherto prevailed was to be laid to the charge of Aristotle, for he brought induction into philo- sophy without sifting it critically, or arranging it in logical order. By the side of a fruitless logic Aristotle had upheld an illogical experience. What great end, then, could be attained by the philosophy that followed him, provided as it BACON AS AN ANTI-ARISTOTELIAN. 153 was with such inefficient weapons? Thus, in Bacon’s eyes, all the “ Idola Theatri” that occupy the field of science are combined under the name of Aristotle. To this point, therefore, he directs all the attacks which he intends for antiquity in general. The name of Aristotle is, as it were, the extremity of a rod that must conduct all the lightnings darted by Bacon against the earlier phi- losophy. That Bacon may not appear unjust to Aristotle, we must consider the name of the latter, when used by the former, as a nomen appe- lativum rather than a nomen proprium. How far he apprehended the veritable Aristotle we shall not pause to inquire, for our inquiry here is not what Aristotle really was, but what he ap- peared in the eyes of Bacon, who attacked in him the theorist, the metaphysician, the formalist, and the empirist — making of himself an anti- Aristotle incarnate. To the Aristotelian “ Organon,” Bacon, in his own “ Organum,” offers a double opposition. He combats the Aristotelian logic with experience, and the Aristotelian experience (which he con- siders the same as the common) with methodical experience. ‘To syllogism he opposes induction ; to Aristotelian induction true induction. His tactics in both cases are the same. He would prove that both syllogism and Aristotelian expe- 154 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. rience are, with respect to physics, equally un- practical and unfruitful. SyLLOGISM is unfruitful, inasmuch as it cannot discover any- thing new, cannot find anything unknown, but can only exhibit, arranged in a consequent order, notions that are already familiar. It is a mere form of thought, that presupposes a given mate- rial to fill it up. But the aim of genuine science is the discovery of a material, not the mere arrange- ment of that which has already been given or handed down. From the known, science would infer the unknown. ‘Thus syllogism, which only arranges what is known, is an useless instrument in the hand of science; that is, of no assistance to her in her investigations, and does not advance her interests in the slightest degree. From syllogistic logic no science can be derived, since, as Bacon observes, it is of no service in the discovery of scientific truth.* Of what does syllogism consist ? Of judgments or premises. And of what do these consist? Of words. But words are mere symbols of notions that are in themselves obscure and * “ Sicut scientiee que nunc habentur inutiles sunt ad inven- tionem operum ; ita et logica que nunc habetur inutilis est ad inventionem scientiarum.”— Nov. Org. I. 11. USELESSNESS OF FORMAL LOGIC. 155 abstract representations of things, made and taken upon trust without due investigation, and circu- lated in the same fashion. Thus, if we reduce syllogism to its ultimate elements, we find that it rests upon obscure and uncertain notions.* These are turned into current coin by Formal logic, and as such are circulated. Thus, this kind of logie, far from conducing to the investigation of truth, rather serves to establish error; so that it is not merely useless, but even injurious. Syllogistie science lives on words alone; encourages not action, but talking; rendering men not inventive, but loquacious, and mere disputation leads to nothing. The art of words does not promote the “regnum hominis,” but merely the “ munus pro- Sessorium.” Experience proceeds differently from this kind of logic, proving not by words, but by deeds; demonstrating ad oculos, experimentalising instead of talking. With the aid of an instrument, it * “Syllogismus ex propositionibus constat, propositiones ex verbis, verba notionum tessere sunt. Itaque si notiones ipsx (id quod basis rei est) confuse sint et temere a rebus abs- tractee, nihil in iis que superstruuntur est firmitudinis.” — Nov. Org. I. 14. T “ Logica que in usu est ad errores (qui in notionibus vul- garibus fundantur) stabiliendos et figendos valet, potius quam ad inquisitionem veritatis ; ut magis damnosa sit quam utilis.” — Nov, Org. I, 12. 156 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. rectifies our sensuous perception, and fits it for the observation of things. ‘“ We must fly to art,” says Bacon, “and must look to demonstration that is governed by art. As for syllogism, which is regarded by Aristotle as an oracle, sentence may be passed on it ina few words. It is, doubtless, useful to the understanding, as a sort of helping hand, in those sciences that are founded on human opinions, as the moral and political, but it is unequal and incompetent to the subtlety and obscurity of natural things. Thus, induction remains our last and only aid in the acquisition of real knowledge. Nor do we, without cause, rest our hopes upon it, since it is able to collect laborious works and the faithful suffrages of things, and present them to the intellect.”* Therefore away with syllogism; let us have * “ (Cogitavit) sequi igitur ut ad artem confugiendum, et de demonstratione que per artem regitur, videndum sit. Atque de syllogismo qui Aristoteli oraculi loco est, paucis sententiam claudendam. Rem esse nimirum in doctrinis que in opinionibus hominum posite sunt, veluti moralibus et politicis, utilem et intellectui manum quandam auxiliarem ; rerum vero naturalium subtilitati et obscuritati imparem et incompetentem. Restare inductionem, tanquam ultimum et unicum rebus subsidium et perfugium ; neque immerito in ea spes sitas esse, ut que opera laboriosa et fida rerum suffragia colligere, et ad intellectum per- ferre possit.”—Cogit. et Visa. ARISTOTELIAN EXPERIENCE. 157 EXPERIENCE. Not, however, Aristotelian experience, for this is just as sterile as syllogism, and no less misses the ultimate object of all scientific research. In a natural state of things, logic ought to discover truths, and experience invent works; the former procuring for us new knowledge, the latter aiding us to new inventions. But the Aris- totelian logic contributes nothing ‘ad inventionem scientiarum ;” the Aristotelian experience contri- butes nothing “ad inventionem operum.” Both are incapable of invention, and therefore both are useless. The Aristotelian experience is sterile from a double cause ; that is to say, it is either a mere description involving an expanse of matter without form (just as the syllogism was an empty form without matter), or “asimple and childish kind of induction, that proceeds by enumeration alone, and therefore arrives not at necessary, but at uncertain conclusions.”* Hence it does not lead to any knowledge of laws, to any interpreta- tion of nature, to any invention, but remains dry and sterile. Or, on the other hand, this Aristo- * “Formam ejusdem (inductionis) meditati sunt admodum simplicem et plane puerilem que per enumerationem tantum procedat, atque propterea precario non necessario concludat.”— Cog. et Visa, 158 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. telian experience at once infers the most general laws from the consideration of a few particular cases, without regarding the negative instances, — without extending its path by a careful com- parison of various cases, or shortening it by the discovery of prerogative instances. It does not discover, but merely abstracts laws, and is thus unmethodical and uncritical,—not investi- gating, but anticipating nature. From single facts to general laws it proceeds as if by flight, not step by step. Its fault is an impatience of delay, which, not allowing any pause to the work of experience, forces it to fly upwards, instead of climbing; so that it misses the goal that it is in such a hurry to reach. It grasps immediately at the highest laws, — determines the primary before it has ascertained the intermediate causes,— hoping by syllogistic art to supply the links wanting in the chain of existence.* An expe- rience of this kind can lead to no experiment properly called,—to no invention; it is therefore as sterile as the syllogism. * The whole of the above passage is an expansion of the following :—‘‘ More impatientes et compendia viarum undique lustrantes, et quedam in certe ponere, circa que, tanquam circa polos, disputationes verterentur, properantes, eam (induc- tionem) tantum ad generalia scientiarum principia adhibuerunt, media per syllogismorum derivationes expedire temere sperantes.” — Cog. et Visa.—J. O. INVENTIVE EXPERIENCE. 159 In the place of this kind of experience, Bacon puts the inventive, which proceeds by another path. “There are, and can be,” he says, “ only two ways for the investigation and discovery of truth. One flies from the senses and particulars to the most general axioms, and from these principles, and their infallible truth, determines and discovers intermediate axioms. And this is the way now p in use. The other constructs axioms from the #* senses and particulars, by ascending continually and gradually, so as to reach the most general axioms last of all, This is the true way, but is yet untried.”* The right way from the par- ticular phenomena to the highest laws of nature is by a series of steps, and this series constitutes the characteristic difference between the Baconian experience and that which had pre- viously prevailed. “The human understanding must not jump and fly from particulars to remote and most general axioms (such as the so-called principles of acts and things), and then, by the infal- * “Due vie sunt, atque esse possunt, ad inquirendam et in- veniendam yeritatem. Altera a sensu et particularibus advolat ad axiomata maxime generalia, atque ex iis principiis eoramque immota veritate judicat et invenit axiomata media ; atque heec via in usu est: altera a sensu et particularibus excitat axiomata, ascendendo continenter et gradatim, ut ultimo loco perveniatur ad maxime generalia; que via vera est, sed intentata,” — Nov, Org. I. 19. 160 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. lible truth of these, test and make out the inter- mediate axioms. This, however, has hitherto been done from the natural bent of the understanding, which has, moreover, been trained and accustomed to this course by the syllogistic form of demon- stration. But we can then only hope well for science, when the ascent shall be made by a true scale, and successive steps, without gap or inter- ruption, first from particulars to minor axioms, then to the intermediate (one above the other), and finally to the most general. For the lowest axioms do not much differ from bare experience; but those which are now deemed the highest and most general are notional and abstract, with nothing solid about them. But the intermediate are those true, solid, and living axioms, upon which depend the affairs and fortunes of mankind. Hence we must not add wings, but rather lead and weights to the human understanding, in order to prevent all jumping and flying.”* * “ Neque tamen permittendum est, ut intellectus a particulari- bus ad axiomata remota et quasi generalissima (qualia sunt principia, que vocant, artium et rerum) saliat et volet; et ad eorum immotam veritatem axiomata media probet et expediat : quod adhuc factum est, prono ad hoc impetu naturali intellectus, atque etiam ad hoc ipsum, per demonstrationes qu fiunt per syllogismum, jampridem edocto et assuefacto. Sed de scientiis tum demum bene sperandum est, quando per scalam veram, et per gradus continuos et non intermissos aut hiulcos, a parti- cularibus ascendetur ad axiomata minora, et deinde ad media, SYLLOGISM AND EXPERIENCE. 161 SYLLoGismM AND EXPpERIENce. These two instruments :of the Aristotelian philosophy stand, as Bacon remarks, in a reci- procal relation; the one supporting, and acting as a supplement to the other. Syllogistie art requires the lower kind of experience, to give a material upon which it may imprint its logical form. Experience requires syllogism, to find intermediate links between phenomena and uni- versal laws. Without experience, syllogism would be devoid of life and motion; without syllogistic art, experience would be aphoristic, and unable even to assume the appearance of systematic order. The mind that is desirous of invention has nothing to expect from either. Its mode of knowledge is logical experience, or inventive logic. Logical experience is distinguished, as experience, from formal logic, which has nothing to do with experience ; and, as logic, from the ordinary expe- alia aliis superiora, et postremo demum ad generalissima. Etet.im axiomata infima non multum ab experientia nuda discrepant. Suprema vero illa et generalissima (que habentur) notionalia Sunt et abstracta, et nil habent solidi. At media sunt axiomata illa vera et solida et viva, in quibus humane res et fortune sites sunt. .... Itaque hominum intellectui non plume addenda, sed plumbum potius et pondera; ut cohibeant omnem saltum et volatum.”—Nov. Org. I. 104. M 162 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. rience, in which there is nothing logical. “ We must apply to ourselves,” says Bacon, “the joke of him who said that wine-drinkers and water- drinkers cannot think alike; especially as it hits the point so well. Now other men, both ancient and modern, have drunk in science, a crude liquor, like water, which has either flowed spontaneously out of the understanding, or has been drawn up by dialectics, as by a wheel from a well. But we drink and pledge others with a liquor made from an infinite number of grapes, and those well ripened, plucked, and collected in picked clusters, then crushed in the winepress, and at last purified and clarified in a vessel. Therefore it is not wonderful that we do not agree with others.” * * «Ttaque dicendum de nobis ipsis quod ille per jocum dixit, presertim cum tam bene rem secet: fieri non potest ut idem sentiant, qui aquam et qui vinum bibant. At ceteri homines, tam veteres quam novi, liquorem biberunt crudum in scientiis, tanquam aquam vel sponte ex intellectu manantem, vel per dialecticam, tanquam per rotas ex puteo haustam. At nos liquorem bibimus et propinamus ex infinitis confectam uvis, iisque maturis et tempestivis, et per racemos quosdam collectis ac decerptis, et subinde in torculari pressis, ac postremo in vase re- purgatis et clarificatis. Itaque nil mirum si nobis cum aliis non conveniat.”—Vov. Org. I. 123. By “ aquam sponte ex intellectu manantem,” Bacon manifestly means syllogism; by “aquam per rotas ex puteo, haustam,” that kind of experience that from a few facts leaps at once to the most general axioms. In the parallel passage of “ Cogitata et Visa,” he expresses the same thought by the words, “ Industria quadam haustum (liquorem).” —Author’s Note. SYMPATHY WITH PLATO. 163 2. BACON’S OPPOSITION AND AFFINITY TO PLATO. — HIS OPINION OF PLATO AND ARISTOTLE, Within the limits of formal philosophy, to which as a whole he is diametrically opposed, Bacon, nevertheless, makes a remarkable distinction be- tween Aristotle and Plato. Of the two, Plato appears to him as belonging to the higher order of mind, as the greater genius. The systems of these philosophical chiefs of classical antiquity are, indeed, both equally removed from a true semblance of nature; the minds of both are prepossessed by “ idols,” but those of Plato are as poetical as those of Aristotle are sophistical.* Little as Bacon participates in the errors of Plato, they appear to him more amiable and natural than those of the other. The imagination, when it errs, is more readily pardoned than the under- standing. Bacon’s philosophical views were far removed from anything like poetry, but he had a lively imagination, and a ready susceptibility for the charms of poetry; and this side of his character was attracted by the poetical Plato. Indeed, this element of poetry in Bacon, which is displayed not only in his preference for Plato, but not unfrequently influences his style, and guides * “ Platonem, tam prope ad poet, quam illum (Aristotelem), ad sophiste partes accedere.”— Cogitata et Visa. M 2 164 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. him in the choice of his examples, proves anew the truth of the felicitous remark once made by Humboldt on the subject of Columbus, that a poetical imagination expresses itself in every great specimen of human character.* Bacon draws a distinction between Plato and Aristotle, precisely the same as that which, by many of the present day, is drawn between Schel- ling and Hegel. In opposition to both of them, he puts correct investigation, which, he asserts, Plato has spoiled by imagination, Aristotle by dialectics. The great example of sophistical phi- losophy, according to Bacon, is Aristotle, who, by his dialectics, spoiled natural science, inas- much as he produced a world from categories. Thus, Bacon reproaches Aristotle with a resolu- tion of all reality into categories ; Plato, with a conversion of reality into imaginary forms; the one setting logical abstraction, the other poeti- cal images, and both alike setting “idols” in the place of things. Plato is mystical and poetical ; Aristotle, dialectical and sophistical. Thus, in his day, did Bacon judge the classical philosophers of antiquity ; and, at the present time, the same judgment is passed by almost everybody upon Schelling and Hegel. We say this without par- tiality; our only interest being in the fact that * « Ansichten der Natur,” Vol. I. p. 256. SCHELLING AND HEGEL. 165 we maintain, namely, that the judgment passed on Schelling and Hegel, at the present day, is not only similar, but literally the same as that formerly pronounced by Bacon on Plato and Aristotle. It is not without reason that many have called atten- tion to the affinity between Hegel and Aristotle, Schelling and Plato. We may even state a ratio: — as the two German idealists are to our own age, so are the two Greeks to the ageof Bacon. We are not speaking here of a distance in point of time, but of scientific magnitude. If nearly everybody now judges of the two German philosophers, just as Bacon judged of kindred spirits among the ancient Greeks, we may regard this identity as an important sign, showing how near the present age has brought itself to the Baconian point of view. It bears witness to an affinity between Bacon’s mode of thought, and that now prevailing. We think too highly of Bacon to construe this sign unfavourably for the present age. Still, there is one thing it does not prove ; namely, that the tendency of our own times to pronounce a verdict against the last systems of philosophy is at all new or original. One thing it does not proclaim (although this is presumed by many, who are ignorant of history), namely, a new epoch! Much more is this turn of thought to be regarded as a mere emanation of that broad, intellectual flood that. M3 166 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. originated with Bacon. On this account, do we examine so carefully, and with such deep interest, the great source itself; on this account do we strive to exhibit to the present generation, as In a clear mirror, the image of Bacon, which it has imitated for the most part unconsciously, but, on the whole, certainly not without cause. Tue PLATonic IDEALISM. Bacon rejects alike the Platonic ideas and the Aristotelian categories ; both are to him abstract, sterile forms, that explain nothing in nature. But the Platonic philosophy regards its Ideas, which, in truth, are merely idols, as the divine originals of the things themselves. It deifies these idols; and thus, to the realistic thinker, appears an apotheosis of error, bribing the understanding through the imagination. Such a thinker must naturally regard it as a science of logical corrup- tion, as a fantastic philosophy. “ For the human understanding,” says Bacon, “is no less exposed to the impressions of fancy, than to those of vulgar notions. For the disputatious and sophistical kind of philosophy ensnares the understanding ; while that other fanciful, bombastic, and, as it were, poetical sort, rather flatters it. There is in man a certain ambition of the intellect, no less than of the will, especially among lofty and FANTASTIC PHILOSOPHY. 167 elevated minds. Of this better kind we have, among the Greeks, a most conspicuous example in Pythagoras, though combined with a coarser and more burdensome superstition; but it appears more subtle and dangerous in Plato and his school. This kind of evil is found also in branches of other systems, where it introduces abstract forms, final and primary causes, frequently omitting the inter- mediate, and the like. Against it, the greatest caution must be used; for the apotheosis of error is the greatest of evils, and the worship of folly may be regarded as the pestilence of the intellect. But in this vanity some of the moderns, with consummate recklessness, have indulged to such an extent, that they have endeavoured to found a natural philosophy on the first book of Genesis, the book of Job, and other sacred writings; thus seeking the dead among the living. And this folly is the more to be checked and restrained, because not only fantastical philosophy, but here- tical religion, results from such an absurd mix- ture of the divine and human. It is, therefore, most wholesome soberly to render unto faith only the things that are faith’s.” * * “Humanus enim intellectus non minus impressionibus phan- tasize est obnoxius, quam impressionibus vulgarium notionum. Pugnax enim genus philosophize et Sophisticum illaqueat intel- lectum: at illud alterum phantasticum et tumidum, et quasi M4 168 FRANCIS BACON € VERULAM. - Aiming at the purity of science, Bacon would, above all, preserve its foundation, physics, from every heterogeneous admixture. ‘“ Natural phi- losophy has not yet been found in a pure state, but corrupt and infected :—in the school of Ari- stotle, by logic; in the school of Plato, by natural theology; in the second school of Plato (that of Proclus and others), by mathematics, which ought to limit natural philosophy, not to generate or create it. But from a pure and unmixed natural philosophy better results are to be hoped.” * Poeticum, magis blanditur intellectui. Inest enim homini qux- dam intellectus ambitio, non minor quam voluntatis; preesertim in ingeniis altis et elevatis. Hujus autem generis exemplum inter Grecos illucescit, preecipue in Pythagora, sed cum super- stitione magis crassa et onerosa conjunctum ; at periculosius et subtilius in Platone, atque ejus schola. Invenitur etiam hoc genus mali in partibus philosophiarum reliquarum, introducendo formas abstractas, et causas finales, et causas primas ; omittendo seepissime medias, et hujusmodi. Huic autem rei summa adbi- benda est cautio. Pessima enim res est errorum Apotheosis, et pro peste intellectus habenda est, si vanis accedat veneratio. Huic autem vanitati nonnulli ex modernis summa levitate ita in- dulserunt, ut in primo capitulo Geneseos et in libro Job et aliis scripturis sacris, philosophiam naturalem fundare conati sint ; inter viva querentes mortua. 'Tantoque magis hxc vanitas in- hibenda venit et coercenda, quia ex divinorum et humanorum malesana admistione non solum educitur philosophia phantastica, sed etiam religio heretica. Itaque salutare admodum est, si mente sobria fidei tantum dentur que fidei sunt.”—Vov. Org. I. 65. * «Naturalis Philosophia adhuc sincera non invenitur, sed infecta et corrupta: in Aristotelis schola per logicam, in Platonis schola per theologiam naturalem; in secunda schola Platonis, lecpltcr tn r)e - Aether Wey ke Rue? nila 4? SIMILARITY TO PLATONISM. 169 Still, notwithstanding this diametrical oppo- sition of principles and tendencies, there is still a philosophical point of contact to be found between _ the greatest idealist of antiquity and the greatest \realist of modern times. caer Tue PLatonic Metuop is akin or homogeneous to the Baconian. In much the same manner does Plato find his ideas; Bacon, the laws of things. The Socratico-Pla- tonic method derives the mental conception from immediate representations; Bacon, from natural phenomena, derives a law. In both cases the course of reasoning is inductive, beginning with particulars, and ascending to the universal. In both cases the induction is of a kind that pro- ceeds slowly and gradually (per gradus con- tinuos) to the universal:— with Plato, to Ideas ; with Bacon, to laws: with Plato, to the original ; with Bacon, to the copy of nature: with Plato, to the final; with Bacon, to the efficient causes of things. And what is the chief point of all, the course of induction is in both cases pursued Procli et aliorum, per mathematicam ; que philosophiam natu- ralem terminare, non generare aut procreare debet. At ex phi- losophia naturali pura et impermista meliora speranda sunt,”— Nov. Org. I. 96. Sn ae eR CR RE 170 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. through negative instances. Following the ex- ample of Socrates, Plato applies the test of a negative instance to all definitions, so that these are continually rectified and purified by con- tradictory instances, which here are not natural phenomena, but definitions or propositions. In the “ Republic,” the idea of justice is under dis- cussion, and it appears to Cephalus that the just man should give to every one his own, and should therefore return what he has borrowed, when he is asked for it. “Is it then just,” asks Socrates, “to return borrowed weapons, where the lender is mad when he asks for them?” Manifestly not. Here is the negative instance ; it shows that the first definition of justice was too broad, and therefore does not meet the point. What Cephalus imagines to be just, is not so in every case. To collect all the examples of the negative instances to be found in Plato, it would be neces- sary to copy out the whole of his dialogues. In the same manner, Bacon uses the negative instance as a test, to discover whether the conditions of natural phenomena that present themselves are essential or not. Plato makes experiments with ideas, as Bacon with things. With both of them, the mode of proof consists in so testing that which is to be proved, as to ascertain whether, in every respect, it will agree with their hypothesis; THE PLATONIC INDUCTION. 171 in other words, whether it will endure the ordeal of negative instances. Thus, both make experi- ments; one logically, the other physically ; one to discover the true idea among our notions, the other to find out the true laws in nature. They proceed by similar roads, viz., per veram inductionem, to opposite goals. Bacon himself perceived this affinity, and it made him prefer Plato to Aristotle. ‘ An induction that is to be useful for the discovery and demonstration of the sciences and arts, should separate nature by proper rejections and exclusions, and then, after a suf- ficient number of negatives, come to an affirma- tive conclusion. This has not yet been done, nor even tried, except by Plato, who certainly makes use of this form of induction to some extent, for the purpose of sifting definitions and ideas.” * The Platonic induction leads to a world of ideas, which is formed by the way of continued abstraction; the Baconian induction leads to a copy of the real world, by the way of continued experience. From Plato’s point of view the real * “At inductio que ad inventionem et demonstrationem scientiarum et artium erit utilis naturam separare debet, per re- jectiones et exclusiones debitas; ac deinde, post negativas tot quot sufficiunt, super affirmativas concludere ; quod adhue factum non est, nec tentatum certe, nisi tantummodo a Platone, qui ad excutiendas definitiones et ideas, hac certe forma inductionis aliquatenus utitur.”— Nov. Org. L 105. 172 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. world itself appears a copy, of which philosophy is to find the original. From the Baconian point of view, on the contrary, the real world appears — as the original, of which philosophy must make a copy. The Platonic abstraction consists in the analysis of ideas; the Baconian, in the analysis of things,—an anatomical dissection of bodies, the *‘dissectio nature,” the “anatomia corporum,” which Bacon requires in lieu of the Platonic abs- traction. “ For we are establishing in the human intellect a true model of the world, such as it is found to be, not such as any one’s reason may have suggested ; but this cannot be effected with- out performing a most diligent dissection and anatomy of the world.” * 3. THE AFFINITY OF BACON TO DEMOCRITUS AND THE ATOMISTS. We now come to the last relation between Bacon and the Greek philosophy, and here we find an indubitable point of contact. Bacon opposes Aristotle on every point, and with all his might. He will have nothing in common with him, deeming that his method is as useless and as * « Etenim verum exemplar mundi in intellectu humano fun- damus; quale invenitur, non quale cuipiam sua propria ratio dictaverit. Hoc autem perfici non potest, nisi facta mundi dis- sectione atque anatomia diligentissima.”—Vov. Org. I. 124. AFFINITY TO THE ATOMISTS. 173 sterile as his doctrines. His affinity to Plato is merely of the formal kind; he finds here his own method, the ¢rue induction, but it is employed for futile ends or useless devices. For the Platonic ideas or imaginations have nothing in common with human life, and therefore cannot have any practical influence upon it. However, there is one doctrine of antiquity which has a material affinity to Bacon, namely, Materialism itself, or, as the ancients called it, the Physiology of the Pra-Socratic period, which stands as the opposite pole to formal philosophy generally. To the Atomistic philosophy of De- mocritus and his disciples, sometimes involun- tarily, sometimes intentionally, Bacon is inclined above all other systems. ‘That earliest philoso- phical age was devoted to a lively contemplation of nature, to the matter of things themselves, not to forms abstracted from them. The principles here laid down for the foundation of things were of a corporeal nature, and coincided with the elements. Bacon’s dislike to formal philosophy occasions and explains his inclination to Ma- terialism. His opposition to Aristotle occasions and explains his affinity to Democritus. Bacon and Democritus form, as it were, two opposite poles to that formal philosophy that governed classical antiquity, and afterwards the scholastic 174 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. middle ages. Democritus is the pole beyond it, Bacon the pole on this side. “It is better to dissect nature than to abstract,” says Bacon, “and this has been done by the school of Demo- critus, which penetrated more deeply into nature than the rest.”* Among all the Greek philoso- phers Bacon distinguishes the Atomists as the most sagacious, observing that they possessed and propagated a sense for true natural science, and were only obscured and, as it were, outshone by the philosophy of Aristotle and Plato, after the Genserics and Attilas—the barbarians of the irruption — had annihilated the scientific sense of the world altogether. For in the days of civilised antiquity the influence of Democritus never ceased. He and the whole age of Pra-Socratic philosophy are opposed by Bacon to the authority of Aristotle. The tendency of Aristotle to busy himself with words, rather than with the living truth of things, is best shown, according to Bacon, by a com- parison of his philosophy with that of others, who were in repute among the Greeks. “ For the homoiomera of Anaxagoras, the atoms of Leu- cippus and Democritus, the heaven and earth of Parmenides, the discord and concord of [Kmpe- docles, the resolution of bodies into the common * +‘ Melius est naturam secare, quam abstrahere, id quod Demo- criti schola fecit, quee magis penetravit in naturam, quam relique.” DEMOCRITUS. 175 nature of fire, and their recondensation, as taught by Heraclitus, have about them somewhat of natural philosophy, and savour of the nature of things, of experience, and of corporeal reality ; while for the most part the physics of Aristotle are nothing but logical terms, and are afterwards treated in his metaphysics under a more imposing name, and as if he were dealing rather with things than with words.” * Among all these natural philosophers of the Greeks Bacon gives the preference to the Atomists, with Democritus at their head. Their theory is the most natural; it penetrates corporeal things in the proper sense of the word, for it traces them to their ultimate particles, and is therefore more materialistic than any other. Democritus laid down the correct principle that matter was eternal, and that, far from being destitute of all shape and form, it was determined from the beginning by motive and forming powers; that matter and form * “Habent enim Homoiomera Anaxagore, Atomi Leucippi et Democriti, Calum et Terra Parmenidis, Lis et Amicitia Empedoclis, Resolutio corporum in adiaphoram naturam ignis et Replicatio eorundem ad densum Heracliti, aliquid ex philo- sopho naturali, et rerum naturam et experientiam et corpora sapiunt; ubi Aristotelis Physica nihil aliud quam dialectics voces plerunque sonet; quam etiam in Metaphysicis sub solen- niore nomine, et ut magis scilicet realis, non nominalis, re- tractavit.”— lVov. Org. I. 63. 176 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. were absolutely inseparable, had never been parted from each other in the nature of things, and therefore were not to be separated, though they might be distinguished in the interpretation of nature. That formless matter, of which Plato, Aristotle, and their disciples talk so much, is not the matter of things, but only the matter of that vague and obscure discourse which is the boast of word-philosophy. The only fault of Democritus ‘consists in this, that he did not arrive at his correct and irrefutable principles by a methodical interpretation of nature, but anticipated them by the mere operation of the unassisted intellect; that is to say, he maintained them metaphysically, instead of proving them physically, by the way of experiment.* This fault of Democritus belongs to * This is the reason why Bacon did not identify his philo- sophy with that of the Atomists. He desired physical, not metaphysical atoms. Physical atoms are corpuscles or particles, i.e. the ultimate and smallest parts of body that we can perceive and exhibit, The atoms, in the metaphysical or strict sense of the word, are mere thoughts, or entia rationis (Gedankendinge), that no investigator of nature has ever yet discovered. ‘This was clearly perceived by Bacon, who therefore says that his method will not lead to a theory of atoms, that presupposes a vacuum, and an immutable matter (both of which are false), but to real particles, such as are discovered to be. [“ Neque prop- terea res deducetur ad Atomum, qui preesupponit vacuum et materiam non fluxam (quorum utrumque falsum est), sed ad particulas veras, quales inveniuntur.”— Nov. Org. Il. 8.] — Author’s Note. DISAGREEMENT WITH THE ATOMISTS. 177 the Greek philosophy in general, the character of which is most distinctly imprinted on the Atomists. Of all the ages of philosophy this earliest age of Greek physiology was most akin to nature and truth, at least so it appeared in the eyes of Bacon, who regarded it as the only one engaged in the serious pursuit of natural science. The follow- ing ages, from Socrates down to Bacon himself, corrupted natural philosophy, and thus brought science in general into a state of ever-increasing degeneracy. All genuine natural philosophy was | spoiled and thrust back, first by the Platonic | doctrine of ideas, which put abstract thoughts | in the place of things; then, further, by the | Aristotelian logic, which for both things and thoughts substituted words; afterwards by the moral philosophy of the Romans; and, last of all, by that mixture of Aristotelian philosophy with Christian theology, which brought barbarism and the perversion of intellect to perfection. That | earliest age, not yet vitiated by false philoso- phy, nor much perplexed by idola theatri, had alone the right instinct, and was alone directed to the right purpose. To carry out this purpose nothing was wanting but scientific means. Without instruments, without method, these earliest na- tural philosophers could not think conformably to experience, or in a truly physical spirit. What N 178 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. could they do but anticipate nature, when they were unable to interpret her in a scientific manner ? Their physics became metaphysics from the very first. They were right in seeking for the prin- ciple of things in the elements, in real natural forces, but these were at once converted, in their view, to general axioms. ‘They discovered their principles rather by a divining glance than by deep investigation, and, being without a secure method of experience, were directed to the un- assisted intellect. They had not a false method, —they had no method at all. The intellect left to itself cannot know anything, it can only fabricate. Thus in Bacon’s eyes the oldest philo- sophy seems, as far as its subject-matter is con- cerned, to be akin to nature and truth, but, with respect to its form, to belong more to imagination than to science. Nature and truth are to be found in it, not as objects of clear knowledge based upon experience, but as a myth projected by the poetical intellect. Here Bacon discovers the affinity between Greek physiology and mytho- logy, and here we have the origin of his views respecting the “ Wisdom of the Ancients.” Physi- ology appears to him as poetry, which indeed it was in the earliest times, and mythology as wisdom in the garb of poetical narrative, that is to say, as a fable or allegory of nature and her ALLEGORICAL INTERPRETATION. 179 powers, — of men and their manners; for what can poetry do but copy reality? In this, there- fore, the oldest poetry and the oldest wisdom agree with each other, that they stand nearest the simple truth, from which they have not been seduced by a false culture, and express, by imagery, the. sense of nature, with which they are inspired. Thus Bacon could only regard the myths of antiquity as allegories, and attempted an allegorical explanation of them in his book on the “* Wisdom of the Ancients.” And at this point of view he arrived, it seems, by two paths. By one he finds in the earliest age scientific myths, — fables that appear as important theories, and, when stripped of their poetical veil, are converted into physiological propositions, that more accord with his own views than all the systems of a later period. But if, in some cases, the myths have evidently an allegorical signifi- cance, why not in many other cases also? If there are scientific why not also moral and political myths? Thus could Bacon reason, and thus, in accordance with such reasoning, could he attempt to apply the allegorical mode of interpretation, that in some cases seemed to be imperatively en- joined, by the nature of things, to many similar cases. Nay, it is not enough to say that he could do this. After the discovery that he thought he N 2 180 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. had made in reviewing the earliest age of the philosophy that had preceded him, he could not do otherwise than prefer the allegoric interpreta- tion of ancient poetry to every other. He was further impelled in this direction by the view which he took of poetry itself; and here we have the other path, to which we have already alluded. The one path leads by induction from a historical fact, which Bacon generalises by applying it to many cases; the other leads by deduction from a general theory to an experiment, which is to confirm the presupposed theory, and exemplify it in a series of instances. Both meet at one point, and this point is Bacon’s “ Wisdom of the Ancients.” The shorter of the two paths, — the one which leads to the goal in a straight line, — is the second, which is the immediate result of Bacon’s theory of poetry. 181 CHAP. VII. THE BACONIAN PHILOSOPHY IN ITS RELATION TO POETRY. WHILE critically reviewing the preceding systems of philosophy, Bacon at last finds himself in the presence of poetry. The only point of contact between his own philosophy and the past is in that earliest age, when science and poetry were still identical. The Baconian mind is most remote from the Aristotelian scholasticism ; in a certain sense it approaches the Platonic, and most of all it accords with the atomistic view of Democritus. Here the Baconian philosophy, and that which preceded it, begin to diverge. They converge as they approach mythology, the poetical age of science, when philosophy and poetry still held intercourse with each other. Hence the interest which Bacon takes in the myths of antiquity. This interest has, in the Baconian philosophy itself, a deeper foundation than is commonly supposed. It is supported by the affinity which Bacon dis- covers between himself and the philosophy of the pre-Socratic age. His interpretation of the ancient myths, and his relation to this kind of N 3 182 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. poetry, may partly, at least, be explained by the position taken by the Baconian with reference to the earlier philosophy ; for this interpretation is, partly, at least, a translation of mythology into Baconian physiology, and is therefore one of the ex- ponents by which Bacon’s relation to his predeces- sors is made clear to us. But his interpretation of the myths may also be immediately deduced from Bacon’s view of poetry in general; and we are the more justified in making this deduction, inas- much as it was made by Bacon himself. His poetical principles preceded and foreshadowed his interpretation of the myths. I. Toe BaconraAn POETICS. The purpose of the Baconian philosophy is to direct the theoretical to the practical mind. The common aim of both should be such a cultivation of man, as will generally be useful in increasing his dominion and promoting his happiness. The practical mind, by means of invention, should remodel the world; the theoretic, conformably to experience, should copy it.* What can this copying of the world be but a description and * In the original there is an antithesis between “ umbilden” and “ abbilden,” which vanishes in translation. — J QO. OFFICE OF POETRY. 183 interpretation? The description of the world is the history of nature and humanity. The inter- pretation of the world is science, by which the information given by history is duly apprehended. History belongs to the memory, which collects and preserves our experiences; science to reason, which reflects on these experiences, and reduces them to general laws. But, besides memory and reason, the theoretic mind has another faculty, — imagination. Hence there is a possibility of a copy of the world made by the imagination, less accurate in detail than the copy in the memory; less regulated by law than the copy in the reason; and distinguished from them both by the circum- stance that it is not found, but invented. Percep- tion and reason should be faithful mirrors, which reflect things unaltered. Imagination, on the other hand, is a magic glass that alters while it reflects. The imaginary copy of the world which it invents is poetry, which, in the realm of the theoretic mind, holds the middle province between history and science. In its operation poetry is akin to the practical mind, for it is inventive; but its end is only theoretical, as it consists in a mere representation of the world. In the mode of representation poetry differs from both science and history ; for nN 4 184 FRANCIS BACON OF VERULAM. these must represent the world as it is, whereas poetry may represent it such as the human heart would desire it to be; these bring the human mind to the level of external things; poetry brings the things to the level of the mind. Therefore poetry was ever thought to have some participa- tion of divineness, because it doth raise and erect the mind, by submitting the shows of things to the desires of the mind, whereas reason doth buckle and bow the mind unto the nature of things.”* What then is poetry from the Baconian point of view?